AESTHETIC ATTITUDE
AESTHETIC ATTITUDE
According to Jerome Stolnitz
in his article ‘The Aesthetic Attitude’, aesthetic attitude is defined as a
disinterested and sympathetic attention to and contemplation of any object of
awareness whatever, for its own sake alone.
Buttressing each part of this
definition, Stolnitz avers that ‘disinterested’ entails that we do not look at
the object out of concern for any ulterior purpose which it may serve. Thus,
the purpose of just having the experiencing the object is the only important
purpose. Our interest must rest upon the object alone. In this disinterested
attention on the object of focus, the aesthetic attitude of disinterestedness
helps us to isolate the object and focus upon it. We ought to, says Stolnitz,
avoid judging, classifying or studying things or works of art, but, simply
savouring the pleasantness and exciting character that things or works of art
carry in themselves. This presents that sharp distinction between being
disinterested and un-interested. While disinterestedness implies sidetracking
judgmental attitudes and focusing on and looking at works of art for what they
are in order become much more interested, uninterestedness implies expunging
any sort of interest in things or aesthetic objects.
Furthermore, the word
‘sympathetic’, Stolnitz opines refers to the way in which we prepare ourselves
to respond to the object. By being sympathetic we accept the object on its own
terms to appreciate it. When we apprehend an object aesthetically, says
Stolnitz, we do so in order to relish its individual quality, whether the
object be charming, stirring, vivid, or all of these. If we are to really
appreciate it, then, we must accept the object in its own terms. We must make
ourselves receptive to the object and set ourselves to accept whatever it may
offer to perception. This implies the need to inhibit any unsympathetic
responses capable of alienating us from the object and are hostile to the
object. To be able to validly assign aesthetic worth on any object, we must be
able to consider such objects aesthetically by allowing the object in question
to speak to us for themselves. And by doing so, we must excise attitudes that
interpose our moral, religious, ethical or political prejudices on the object
in view, as this disrupts the aesthetic attitude. Milton’s sonnet “On the Late
Massacre in Piedmont” for instance, is a ringing protest called forth by an
event which occurred shortly before the writing of the poem. But while, we may
employ modern parameters in offhandedly judging it, the heated questions of
religion and politics which enter into it seem very remote to us now.
To be ‘sympathetic’ then in aesthetic experience,
means giving the object the chance to speak for itself and to show how it can
be interesting to perception.
More
so, the word ‘attention’ in the definition of aesthetic attitude begs to be
clarified. By attention, Stolnitz asseverates, we want to make the value of the
object come fully alive in our experience. When listening to a rhythmically
exciting piece of music which absorbs us with its energy and movement, or when
we read a novel which creates great suspense, we give our earnest attention to
it and in doing so, exclude almost everything else in our surroundings.
Although attention is always a matter of degree, but to whatever extent it does
so, experience is aesthetic only when an object holds our attention.
However,
Stolnitz opines that aesthetic attention is accompanied by activity. This
activity is either evoked by disinterested perception of the object, or else is
required by it. But, focusing upon the object and acting in regard to it, is
not all that is meant by aesthetic attention. To savour fully the distinctive
value of the object, we must be attentive to its frequently complex and subtle
details. This brings to the fore the necessity of discrimination. One could
fail to perceive the individuality of every work of art; that one symphony is
different in sound from a piece of long-hair music; and that one lyric poem is
to be distinguished from another, if one does not develop discriminating
attention to art works.
On
the whole, says Stolnitz, any object at all can be apprehended aesthetically,
that is, no object is inherently unaesthetic. This is evidenced in the fact
that, human beings have found perceptual enjoyment in things which people of
earlier times or other cultures judged to be uninviting or unaesthetic. Thus,
the aesthetic attitude is an impersonal, disinterested and sympathetic
attention to an object of focus, an attitude that allows the object speak for
itself and avoids transposing prejudices, biases and preconceptions on any
object of focus whatsoever.
George
Dickie in ‘The Myth of the Aesthetic Attitude’ charts a different and critique-like
course. He argues here that that
the notion of the aesthetic attitude proposed by Jerome Stolnitz is a myth, which
misleads aesthetic theory.
Dickie begins by criticizing the character of disinterested
attention in Stolnitz’s definition of the aesthetic attitude. According to
Dickie, it can make sense to speak, for example, of listening disinterestedly
to music only if it makes sense to speak of listening interestedly to music.
Using Stolnitz’s definition of ‘disinterestedness’, two situations would have
to be described as ‘listening with no ulterior purpose (disinterestedly) and
‘listening with an ulterior purpose (interestedly). Two people for instance
could listen to the same piece of music, one to analyze it and prepare for an
examination, and the other with no ulterior motive. While they both listen,
they both also differ in motives or intentions. Thus, says Dickie, the apparent
perceptual distinction (that is, listening disinterestedly or interestedly) is
actually a motivational or an intentional distinction. Motive or intention differs
from action. Dickie demonstrates that the only difference between the listening
of two listeners is their purpose and suggests that in reality there is nothing
different about their attention at all. Therefore, Dickie argues that the
notion of disinterestedness cannot be used to refer to a special kind of
attention. Rather, disinterestedness is a term which is used to make clear that
an action has certain kinds of motives. Attending to an object has its motives
but the attending itself is neither interested nor disinterested.
Furthermore, and in a bid to further show the untenability
of the disinterestedness character, while Stolnitz thinks that we cannot
criticize while appreciating a work of art, because, criticism will unhealthily
interfere with appreciation, Dickie employs the art critic analogy to refute
this claim. According to Dickie, the art critic surely has an ulterior purpose,
namely, to analyze and evaluate the object he/she observes, and if Stolnitz is
to be right, then insofar as a person functions as a critic then he/she cannot
function as an appreciator.
On this note, Dickie avers that Stolnitz confuses a
perceptual distinction with a motivational one. But since, as earlier evinced,
attending to an object has its motives but the attending itself is neither
interested nor disinterested, the critic differs from other percipients only in
his/her motives and intentions and not in the way in which he/she attends to a
work of art.
More so, while Dickie develops a convincing argument against
Stolnitz’s theory of the aesthetic attitude, he does only really focus on one
aspect of it - disinterestedness - and does not effectively address the idea of
sympathetic attention, for example. In his argument, Stolnitz stresses the
importance of considering all the aspects of his definition of the aesthetic
attitude, so for this reason, Dickie’s attempt at challenging Stolnitz’s theory
is counter-productive.
MY POSITION
Aesthetics is the science of ‘oughtness’
and not of ‘isness.’ Stolnitz’s proposal is a presentation of an ideal, that
is, what ought to be done. That such a proposal is for now not achieved does
not preclude the need for an insistence on striving for the ‘ought.’ Dickie
conflates what is with what ought and this is the provenance of the problem
incurred in his theses.
I am fully in favour of Stolnitz’s
theses because they speak of the need to approach works of art without being
surrounded by a montage of prejudices and biases. On this note, his theses
should not be understood as implying the total absence of our ethical,
religious, sexual affiliations. While these conceptual primitives might be
somewhat altogether present, there is a need to transcend them.
Comments
Post a Comment