Aristotle's concept of Potency and Acts


Introduction
Potentiality and actuality are important terms and principles Aristotle used to analyze motioncausalityethics, and physiology in his PhysicsMetaphysicsNicomachean Ethics and De Anima, which is about the human psyche.[1] In this paper, we shall discuss in details the concept of Aristotles potentiality and actuality. To achieve this, we shall discuss the etymology of the terms, history, definition, division of act and division of potency, relationship between act and potency, and then a final conclusion.

Etymology
Potentiality and potency are translations of the Ancient Greek word dunamis as it is used by Aristotle as a concept contrasting with actuality. Its Latin translation is "potentia", root of the English word potential. Dunamis is an ordinary Greek word for possibility or capability. Depending on context, it could be translated potency, potential, capacity, ability, power, capability, strength, possibility, force and is the root of modern English words dynamic, dynamite, and dynamo.[2]
Actuality is often used to translate both energeia and entelecheia. "Actuality" comes from Latin actualitas and is a traditional translation, but its normal meaning in Latin is "anything which is currently happening".[3]

History
Prior to the doctrine of act and potency, there were two great errors concerning the problem of change and stability in beings: the static monism of Parmenides and the philosophy of becoming of Heraclitus.

Parmenides was the first formulator of the principle of non-contradiction, he denied the possibility of motion or change in the world, adopting a monistic conception of the world. Parmenides of Elea and the Eleatic school held that A thing either is or is not. If it is, it is being; if it is not, it is nonbeing or nothing. That which comes to be, before the change either is or is not. If it is, it is being; if it is not, it is non-being. But we cannot say that before the change it is; for this would mean that it comes to be what it is already, that being comes to be being. Obviously a thing cannot come to be what it already is. On the other hand, it is equally impossible that what comes to be is not before the change; for this would mean that non-being comes to be, that non-being becomes being. But it is clear that non-being cannot come to be being. Hence,  Parmenides concluded that change or becoming is positively[4]
unintelligible and therefore impossible. Concerning the changes, we see around us, Parmenides held that: since change is impossible, our senses deceive us when they testify to the reality of change; for reason clearly shows that all change is a contradiction in terms. It follows that all reality is but one being. For whatever is different has to differ either by being or by non-being; now what differs by non-being or nothing is not different; while on the other hand things cannot differ by being because being is precisely that by which they are the same. In this way Parmenides was led to static monism monism, because he admitted the existence of only one thing; static, because he denied that this one thing was subject to any change whatsoever. [5]

Heraclitus, affirmed that only change was real, stability was an illusion, there being no fixed natures or essences in things, everything being in a constant flux; there are no stable beings but only change or becoming. He held that reality is not being but becoming or change. Whatever seems to be is nothing but a deception, just as a stream may seem to be always the same, but in reality is always changing.[6]

Aristotle’s Act and Potency
Aristotle arrived at a solution to the Parmenidean and Heraclitean errors concerning change and stability in beings with his doctrine of act and potency. With Parmenides, Aristotle maintained that being is real, and with Heraclitus, he asserted that change is real. Being, he says, ‘is distinguished in respect of potency and complete reality. In other words, Aristotle admits that there is a middle ground, not between being and non-being, but between being-in-act and non-being, and this middle ground is called being-in-potency.[7]
Thus when we say that a thing comes to be, this does not mean that non-being becomes being, but merely that being-in-potency becomes being-in-act, and this does not imply any contradiction. Therefore, being and change are both intelligible, and there is no reason to reject the reality of either. Unlike the view of Parmenides, the change or motion that we see around us is definitely real; it is the passage from being in potency to being in actuality. It is the successive actualization of the potency. For example, hot water is in a state of actuality and cold water is in a state of potentiality towards being hot water. [8]

Potency is the capacity to have a perfection while act is the perfection which a subject possesses. Act is contrasted to potency, which is the potentiality to receive the perfection or act. Potency and act are directly known through experience as correlative to each other. In the case of potency its very constitution is to be directed towards some type of act. [9]
potency may be described by means of its relationship to act as the capacity for an act. While, as a matter of fact, it is true that most acts presuppose potency, this is not so because they are acts, but because they are limited acts. Act as act merely implies perfection, and not that this perfection is limited.[10]

Act and potency are considered under two aspects, namely, the physical and the metaphysical. Regarding the physical aspect, act and potency form the elements that make change or motion understandable. Here, what is actual cannot be at the same time potential and vice versa. Hot water cannot be cold water at the same time and in the same respect. Change is the transition between being in potentiality and being in actuality.[11]
Regarding the metaphysical aspect, act and potency form the stable constituent principles of all finite beings, so much so that the potency, even after having been made actual, continues to be a co-principle of its corresponding act. [12]
Potency is that which can receive an act or already has it. This statement implies a number of things:
·         potency is distinct from act
·         act and potency are not complete realities but rather principles or aspects found in things
·         potency is to act as the imperfect is to the perfect
·         in itself, potency is not a mere privation of act but is a real capacity for perfection.


1. Potency is Really Distinct from Act. potency is characterized as being the capacity to have an act or by being a receptive subject, and is therefore distinct from act. “The constituent principles of a reality which are called potency and act must be really distinct. For that which perfects cannot be really the same as that which is perfectible; otherwise the perfectible would give itself an act which it does not have, so that being would come from non-being. Moreover, if potency and act were not really distinct, that which limits and that which is limited would be really the same, so that act would limit itself.[13]
2. Act and Potecy are Not Complete Realities but Rather Principles or Aspects Found in Things. Act and potency are the distinct co-principles of a finite thing. Potency and act are not “things” since they are not fully constituted entities with an independent status of their own; rather, they are the intrinsic principles of a finite being, intrinsic co-principles which we find in things, the intrinsic principles of being which, in union with each other, constitute or comprise finite beings. Therefore, we affirm that potency and act so divide being that whatever exists is either pure act (God), or is necessarily composed of potency and act as its first intrinsic principles (which is the case with all finite beings).[14]
3. Potency is to Act as the Imperfect is to the Perfect. act means perfection, a completion, something determinate. Potency, on the other hand, is an imperfection, a capacity for perfection. The fully finished marble statue of  St. Dominic is something determinate, a perfection, something in act, while the shapeless block of marble that was the initial material that was used for the statue would be the determinable, the imperfect, the potency, the potentiality for perfection.[15]
4. In Itself Potency is not a Mere Privation of Act but a Real Capacity for Perfection. The external sense of sight, when not in use, is not a mere privation, but is at that very moment potentially capable of being actualized by the actual operation of seeing, which is a perfection.[16]

Division of Potency
The fundamental division of real potency is between passive potency and active potency. Passive potency is the capacity a thing has to be changed by another as other, while active potency is the power to effect a change in another as other.[17]
Passive potency is the capacity to receive, while active potency is the capacity to act or do, the power to act or do. Passive potency is the capacity of a thing to be changed by another, while active potency is the principle of activity in an agent. Passive potency is a receptive potency, a capacity or principle which can be acted upon, while active potency is a power or principle of action, such as the power of sight or the power of hearing.[18]

1.      Active Potency. As examples of active potency, consider the capacity that a man has for sensing, thinking, or willing. Capacities of this sort (usually designated as powers) share partly in the nature of potency and partly in the nature of act. Inasmuch as a power or a faculty is itself a certain kind of perfection it may be designated as an act. Thus the capacity that a man has to think and reason is in a limited sense an act. However, if we compare the power itself – that is, as a mere capacity for doing something – with the actual exercise of that power, we are then entitled to speak of it as an active potency, because the mere possession of that power is not the same as its actual use. It is from this latter point of view, then, that a power is characterized as ‘potency.’[19]
2.      Passive potency is the capacity for receiving an act. We have entitative potency and potency in the order of form.[20]
·         Entitative Potency. In all finite things the act of being is a received act. The recipient principle of this act – that is, the principle which receives it – is what we call ‘entitative’ potency. [21]
·         Potency in the order of form. Corresponding to the two types of act in the order of form there are also two kinds of potency: (i) Potency for receiving a substantial form. this is primary matter which is pure passive potency; (ii) Potency for receiving an accidental form. This latter is the potency in an already existing subject for receiving any act that is ‘superadded’ to its nature or essence. A diamond, for example, is in potency for being cut (to various shapes and sizes) by a jeweler.[22]
The metaphysical character of potency as a capacity to receive an act pertains to passive potency. However, it is not a homogeneous reality, but one which is found at different levels.[23] We can distinguish three basic types of passive potency and their corresponding acts:
a)      prime matter and substantial form. In bodily substances there is an ultimate substratum, prime matter, in which substantial form is received. This form determines the matter, and thereby forms one or another type of corporeal substance, such as iron, water or oxygen. Prime matter is the ultimate potential substratum, since it is of itself pure potency, a merely receptive subject which lacks any actuality of its own. The substantial form is the first act which prime matter receives.[24]
b)      substance and accidents. All substances, whether material or purely spiritual, are subjects of accidental perfections, such as qualities or relations. Unlike prime matter, the substance is a subject which is already in act through the form, but which is of itself in potency with respect to the accidents.[25]
c)      essence and act of being. The form, in turn, whether it is received in matter or not, is no more than a determinate measure of participation in the act of being. The essences ‘man,’ ‘dog,’ ‘pine tree,’ and ‘uranium,’ for instance, are different ways of participating in being. With respect to the act of being, everything is a limiting receptive potency – from the separated forms, to the composite of matter and form, down to the accidents (which participate in the act of being through their union with the substance).[26]

Division of Act
Pure Act and Mixed Act. Pure act in the absolute sense is act which admits of no potentiality in any order whatsoever. Such an act would neither be a co-principle united to a limiting potency nor would it be in potency to any act of a superior order. Pure act in the absolute sense is God Himself, Who is Pure Act of Being. [27]

Mixed act is act which is received into potency, or it is act which is in potency to act of another order. Mixed act is either entitative or formal.[28]
Entitative act is the very act of being of a finite thing. Entitative act is a mixed act inasmuch as it is received into a potency which limits it, not inasmuch as it is in potency to further act, for esse is the ultimate act.[29]
Formal act, the act of essence, act in the order of essence, is the act by which a thing is determined and perfected in its species; e.g., substantial form.[30]
First Act and Second Act. Formal act may be understood as either first formal act or as second formal act First formal act is act which does not presuppose an anterior act, but awaits a subsequent act; e.g., substantial form.[31]
Second formal act, on the other hand, is act which presupposes an anterior act; e.g., an accident. Therefore, second act is accidental act. Kreyche explains that by ‘formal’ act, or ‘act in the order of form’ we mean any act which causes a thing, not simply to be, but to be specified according to one or another of the determinate modes of being. Formal act may be taken in one of the two following senses: a) First formal act. By first formal act, we mean one which determines or specifies a thing according to its essence or nature. It is that act by virtue of which a thing is one kind of being rather than another (for example, a rabbit rather than a horse). The first formal act of material things is their substantial form ; b) Second Formal Act. By second formal act, we mean any act that is a further modification or determination of an already existing subject. The addition of a second formal act, though it genuinely affects its subject, does not in any way change the nature of the subject that it modifies. Thus any accidental perfection that a thing has (such as, say the sharpness of an alligator’s teeth) is related to it (in our example, the alligator), as a second formal act.[32]

The Relation Between Act and Potency as Constitutive Principles of Being
Regarding the relation between act and potency as principles of being, we can state the
following:
·         Potency is the subject in which the act is received
·         Act is limited by the potency which receives it
·         Act is multiplied through potency
·         Act is related to potency as that which is participated to the participant
·         The act-potency composition does not destroy the substantial unity of being.
1. Potency is the Subject in which the Act is Received. We look at a man, for example, and begin to know his various perfections (acts), like the color of his hair, eyes and skin, without ever denying that these perfections reside in that person (potency), who is the subject of these perfections (acts).[33]
2. Act is Limited by the Potency which Receives It. Every act received in a subject is limited by the capacity of that subject. The perfection of redness in an apple is limited by the substance apple, its recipient. An apple can only contain as much redness as the dimensions of that fruit allow. Unreceived act is in itself unlimited, and when one finds limited instances of act, it is because of a potency which receives and limits it.[34]
3. Act is Multiplied Through Potency. The same act can be present in many individuals which can receive it, as for example, when the specific perfection “apple” is possessed by many individual apples because it is present in a potency, namely, prime matter. The same substantial form is multiplied in many individuals of the same species. Accidents (acts) are also multiplied by their respective potencies, namely substances. The accident “red,” for example, is multiplied insofar as there are many objects having that same color.[35]
4. Act is Related to Potency as that Which is Participated to the Participant. The doctrine of act and potency can be understood using the theory of participation. To participate means to have something in part or something in a partial manner. This presupposes that there are other subjects that possess the same perfection, none of them possessing that said perfection in full.[36]
Also, in participation, the subject cannot be identical to what it possesses; the subject merely possesses this perfection by participation only. The subject of participation has the perfection, possesses the perfection; he is not the perfection, he doesn’t have the perfection by essence, that is, in a full and exclusive manner, by being identical with it. Creatures have the act of being while God is the Act of Being by Essence, that is, Essence and Act of Being are identical in the Divine Being. Now, while pure actuality is act by essence, the relationship of act and potency is one of participation. The subject (potency) capable of receiving a perfection (act) is the participant, and the act itself is that which is participated in by the subject.[37]
5. The Act-Potency Composition does not Destroy the Substantial Unity of a Being. Act and potency are not subsistent beings in themselves but rather constituent principles of finite beings. They are not things but rather the co-principles of a thing. Potency is by nature a capacity for perfection, a capacity towards an act, to which it is essentially ordered and without which it would not be able to exist at all (prime matter [potency], for example, exists for the form [act], without which it simply would not exist). Potency’s union with its act cannot therefore give rise to two individual things, two separate beings.[38]

Conclusion
So far, we have been able to discuss in details the basics of Aristotle’s act and potency. From the discussion, it is obvious that Aristotle brought about those concepts to solve the problems and errors of change and static which has been in existence. Aristotle did not only address the errors but also made important input in philosophy.



REFERENCE
Primary source:
Paul Gerard Horrigan, Ph.D, Act And Potency 2009.

Secondary sources
Aristotle on Science The Posterior Analytics. Proceedings of the eight symposium aristotelicum held in padua from semtember 7 to 15, 1978. Edited by Enrico Berti
ARISTOTLE, Metaphysics, IX, 1, 1045b 34.
C. A. HART, Participation and the Thomistic Five Ways, “The New Scholasticism,” 26 (1952), pp. 267-282
H. J. KOREN, Introduction to the Science of Metaphysics, B. Herder, St. Louis, 1965, pp. 105-106.
W.D. Ross, Aristotles’s Physics.  A revised text with introduction and commentary. oxford at the clarendon press. 1936

Internet sources


[4] Paul Gerard Horrigan, Ph.D, Act And Potency 2009.
[5] H. J. KOREN, Introduction to the Science of Metaphysics, B. Herder, St. Louis, 1965, pp. 105-106.
[6] H. J. KOREN, Introduction to the Science of Metaphysics, B. Herder, St. Louis, 1965, pp. 105-106.
[7] ARISTOTLE, Metaphysics, IX, 1, 1045b 34.
[8] Paul Gerard Horrigan, Ph.D, Act And Potency 2009.
[9] ibid
[10] ibid
[11] ibid
[12] ibid
[13] Paul Gerard Horrigan, Ph.D, Act And Potency 2009.
[14] ibid
[15] ibid
[16] ibid
[17] R. P. PHILLIPS, Modern Thomisic Philosophy, vol. 2 (Metaphysics), Newman, Westminster, MD,1935, pp. 180-181.
[18] H. Renard, The Philosophy of Being, Bruce, Milwaukee, 1950, p. 30.
[19] ibid
[20] ibid
[21]ibid
[22] Paul Gerard Horrigan, Ph.D, Act And Potency 2009.
[23] ibid
[24] ibid
[25] ibid
[26] ibid
[27] Paul Gerard Horrigan, Ph.D, Act And Potency 2009.
[28] ibid
[29]ibid
[30] ibid
[31] ibid
[32] ibid
[33] Paul Gerard Horrigan, Ph.D, Act And Potency 2009.
[34] ibid
[35] ibid
[36] Paul Gerard Horrigan, Ph.D, Act And Potency 2009.
[37] C. A. HART, Participation and the Thomistic Five Ways, “The New Scholasticism,” 26 (1952), pp. 267-282
[38] Paul Gerard Horrigan, Ph.D, Act And Potency 2009.
s

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

SUMMARY OF PROVIDENTISSIMUS DEUS, ENCYCLICAL LETTER OF POPE LEO XIII ON THE STUDY OF THE HOLY SCRIPTURE.

summary and appraisal of chapters one, two and three of the book The African Origin of Greek Philosophy: An Exercise in Afrocentrism, by Innocent C. Onyewuenyi.

THE LAST THREE WAYS TO PROVES GOD'S EXISTENCE BY THOMAS AQUINAS