BERTRAND RUSSELL’S THEORY OF DESCRIPTIONS
BERTRAND
RUSSELL’S THEORY OF DESCRIPTIONS
Bertrand Russell’s theory of descriptions demonstrates
an attempt to correctively react to the flaws inherent in Alexius Meinong’s
theory of objects, in which whatever can be conceived and talked about is
considered something real. The theory of descriptions has been generally an
interesting subject in the philosophy of language. Ordinarily, language aids us
in offering appropriate descriptions. It is supposed to report facts, state of
affairs and phenomena in general. Proceeding from this point, we see that in
giving descriptions, naming is important. Naming, according to John Locke,
enables us to demarcate explicatively different objects. We differentiate a
mango tree from a palm tree by giving them names. From Frege, we began to see
names as descriptions or descriptions as names. Descriptions that have
reference are said to name what they refer. Ever since the time of Frege, the
question of descriptions has been controversial. The height of its controversy
is associated with the Russellian treatment of this subject.
Russell, in his theory of descriptions,
talked about definite and indefinite descriptions. The primary focus of his
theory of descriptions is on the anomaly of improper reference. This however
affects his entire theory of meaning. For Bertrand Russell, we have two sorts
of descriptions. The first is definite description of the sort ‘the so-and-so’. The second description
is called indefinite or ambiguous description of the sort ‘a so-and-so’. The distinguishing marks are that in the first, the
definite article ‘the’ is used while
in the second, the indefinite article ‘a’
is used. If I say ‘a certain man accosted me on the way’, I am not specific and
definite about the person that accosted me, but when I say ‘the man in blue
shirt accosted me’, I am definite and specific. The problem with indefinite
descriptions is that they are ambiguous and confusing in matters of reference.
There is a difference between casual and authentic expression of a sentence.
Mere expression of the so-and-so does not refer necessarily, but the active
expression necessarily refers to an object indicated either by pointing or
specifying the reality of the object referred to.
Bertrand Russell discovered that
albeit every definite description gives the impression that it refers, not
every definite description actually refers. When one says, ‘the present queen
of Nigeria’, any person not at home with the political system in Nigeria will
believe that Nigeria has a queen because of the use of the definite article
‘the’. It is taken for granted that nobody who knows the rule governing the use
of the definite article ‘the’ will use it in a sentence, and for an entity that
does not exist. But, in our use of language, Russell draws our attention to the
fact that there are many suppositions, making it necessary to scrutinize every
sentence of the definite description, in order to ascertain whether they
actually refer or are misleading statements masquerading as properly referring
statements.
In order to take care of such
misleading statements, Russell opines that all descriptions of ‘the so-and-so’
should be done away with. The only properly referring terms are what he calls
logically proper names, that is, the indexicals or pronouns. This is because,
for him, these indexicals are used in such a way as to indicate what is being
referred to. Russell argues that since names are about persons, things, place
and so on, they are disguised descriptions, and like most descriptions, are
susceptible to the same pitfalls of being ambiguous and misleading.
While people like Meinong
think that merely conceiving abstract entities like Unicorn is capable of
conferring existence on them, Russell thinks this is only a dubious way of
using the term ‘existence’. According to Russell, a ‘unicorn’ is an indefinite
description which describes nothing, and as such, has no meaning in the context
of reality. Though a significant statement could be made using unicorn, unicorn
does not by that fact constitute part of the reality of the statement. Things
do not just become real by being incorporated into a significant statement.
Russell’s theory of definite
descriptions therefore refers to the use of the definite article ‘the’ in our
expressions. ‘The’ connotes definiteness but does not guarantee existence. How
then do we take care of the problem of using the definite article in
expressions that actually do not refer? Is it through the application of
certain verifiability criteria or, as suggested in logic, through the
employment of quantifiers? We have universal and existential quantifiers, (x)
and (Ex) respectively. For Russell, universal quantifiers guarantee that there
is something that exists to which we are attributing a given quality or
describing or referring to in our expression. Whatever is in the world is a
particular, definite and real. Names are symbols, which are supposed to
directly designate these individual entities. When names fail to serve this
function, they give rise to multiple problems and hinder meaning. A name is
said not to be part of the fact asserted or of falsehood if our expression is
false. It is rather part of the symbolism by which we express our thought. A
name must name something and whatever name that does not name something, says
Russell, is a false name.
Furthermore, Russell argues
that the descriptions of ‘a so-and-so’ and ‘the so-and-so’ when analyzed will
show whether the name names something. That means that every description tells
us something about something. There must be the object of our reference if the
description is to be significant. Russell, however, concludes that all
descriptions, whether definite or indefinite (of the type “the present king of
France is bald”) is not a name but a complex symbol. A name is a simple symbol.
But then, there are names that feature as descriptions on their own. For
example, when we ask whether Homer existed, we use Homer as an abbreviated
description to refer to the author of the Iliad and the Odyssey. This is the
case with all so-called proper names. This is why Russell opts for what he
calls logically proper names.
On the whole, when a
description asserts of a non-existent entity that it has a given quality, it is
false because the subject does not exist. This is called primary utterance. But
if we assert of a non-existent entity that it does not have a given quality, it
is true because after all the subject does not exist in the first place and
because it does not exist, everything about it is negative. This is called
secondary utterance. For example, ‘the present king of France is bald’ and ‘the
present king of France is not bald’: Russell, therefore, views with disgust the
expression of any statement that does not contain reality. He sees it as
offending that feeling for reality which ought to be preserved even in the most
abstract studies.
CRITIQUES
OF RUSSELL’S THEORY OF DESCRIPTIONS
Peter F. Strawson is one key figure who attempted to
show the untenability of Russell’s submissions. According to Strawson, Russell
was wrong to think that the mere mentioning of a definite description is all there
is in determining its meaning, reference and truth-value. Descriptions are put
to different uses and it will be wrong to conclude that if an expression is
meaningless in one aspect of its use, that it is for that reason meaningless whenever
it is used. For instance, the pronoun ‘I’ as an expression that uniquely refers
does not refer to anybody when it stands alone. It must be used in a sentence,
and, in the sentence, it acquires its meaning and also refers properly. ‘I’ as
an expression when used by different people carry different imports because of
the dimension of utterance.
Others
like Keith Donnellan aver that Russell’s theory could be refuted by using what
Donnellan calls the referential-attributive distinction. According to
Donnellan, Russell’s theory of descriptions accords well with the referential
but not with the attributive. Not every mentioning is referential. Some could
be attributive. Attributive use is intentional while referential is supposed to
be literal. We can attribute, that is assign meaning-reference depending on our
intention. And in this case, mentioning is not referring.
Comments
Post a Comment