FRANKFURT SCHOOL AND THE CRITICAL THEORY


FRANKFURT SCHOOL AND THE CRITICAL THEORY



OUTLINE
1.0    INTRODUCTION

2.0    CONTEXT OF RISING
2.1    Glance of Marxism
2.2    Literature Against Marxism

3.0    FAILURES OF PREVENTION
3.1    Institute for Social Research
3.2    German Prewar Context
3.3    The Employment of The Wonder Minds

4.0    IMPACTS OF CRITICAL THEORY
4.1    The Initiation  of The Critical Theory
4.2    Critique of The Marxian Ideology
4.3    Critique of Western Civilization

5.0    PROVIDENTIAL EXILE IN AMERICA
5.1    Escaping Nazism
5.2    Fertility of The Project
5.3    Birth of The Analytic Philosophy
6.0  CONCLUSION


1.0        INTRODUCTION
The principle of existence in relation with the world of socio-economic enterprise, gives a clear reflection of the dawn and flight of the Frankfurt School. This inherent and essential feature is a construct of what comprise of its history, theories, and political interest. Historically, we see the trends and accounts of occurrences that interplay in the universe; which draws more closely to the circles of revolution. A revolution of this kind is a vivid depiction of the relationship that abounds in variant perspectives.[1] Among them are the terrains of liberal manifestations in the Western philosophical landscape, modern civilization in the wake of the socialist and capitalist structure of the society; and a class of industrial and rational innovations, among others.
All these phases of developments indicated above are major pointers to the perimeters of existential realities; in the light of “rational criticism and analytic theory,” which are represented by the systematic tool of the School of Frankfurt –“The Critical Theory.”[2] It becomes a mandate to state the necessity of this “systematic tool,” whose influential presence led to the influx of radical liberation and downturn, in the center of the socialist and capitalist human society.[3]
By way of methodology and as a plan to develop the subject matter of this paper, an examination of the following contents will be underscored in this order: the context of rising, the failures of prevention, the impacts of critical theory, providential exile in America; and then the sense of an ending- the conclusion. It is on the note of this responsibility, that we give an exposition of the topic: “The Frankfurt School and the Critical Theory.”


2.0 CONTEXT OF RISING
2.1 Glance of Marxism
Marxism is an economic and social system based upon the political and economic theories of Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels. Marxism is summed up as “a theory in which class struggle is a central element in the analysis of social change in Western societies.”[4] Marxism is the antithesis of capitalism which is defined as “an economic system based on the private ownership of the means of production and distribution of goods, characterized by a free competitive market and motivation by profit.” Marxism is the system of socialism of which the dominant feature is public ownership of the means of production, distribution, and exchange.[5]
Marx’s concept of social science was explicitly political, as was his activity as a social scientist, in contrast to the views that social science can be “above politics” or “balanced”, that social science can be apolitical or at least neutral between competing political positions. His concept of science was formed in a peculiarly Germanic tradition. The other two elements- socialism and political economy arrived in 1841, when Marx was in contact with Moses Hess.[6] Marx’s social science was in place as a projected synthesis as early as 1842, though this perspective is available to us only because his early articles, manuscripts and correspondence have now become available.
In his own time, Marx’s thoughts reached the public only through the unexpected writings and journalism.[7] What Marx had in mind was neither Hegelian philosophical system not in the style of Hess. Rather he proposed a unified science that was social not just in its subject matter but in its very presuppositions. For Marx, natural science was not knowledge of inanimate objects such as discovered by individuals doing pure research, but rather an activity within society itself, producing knowledge that would profoundly influence all humanity through technological applications in industry.[8] Social science would be historical and political in its very foundations, seeing every human phenomenon as developing, rather than static; and it would be knowledge for a purpose, namely to promote the emancipation of hu­mankind from class conflict and the transformation of society into a realm of freedom.[9]
According to Marx, there is a “legal and political superstructure" and cor­responding forms of social consciousness. These have developed through various stages into the modern class struggle and the democratic politics of constitutional revolution. Marx aimed to make the two coincident. From this it followed that a major study of modern industrial production would be central to any convincing social science, and that it would be a critical analysis written to promote the political interests of the working class in a democratizing social revolution.[10]
Marx read a political economists whose view is that industrial capitalism was socially progressive, at least in the longer term, and that in order to get to the longer term, it would be necessary, albeit regrettable, to tolerate the poverty and misery from which new wealth and new commodities were generated. By contrast, Marx suspected that capitalism would be subject to economic crises and normative absurdity as the gap between rich and poor widened, and as the gulf between potential productivity and actual production grew more visible.[11]
2.2 Literature Against Marxism
Some contemporary supporters of Marxism argue that many aspects of Marxist thought are viable, but that the corpus is incomplete or somewhat outdated in regards to certain aspects of economic, political or social theory. They may therefore combine some Marxist concepts with the ideas of other theorists such as Max Weber: for example, the Frankfurt school. V. K. Dmitriev and Ladislaus Von Bortkiewicz’s subsequent critics have alleged that Marx's value theory and law of the tendency of the rate of profit to fall are internally inconsistent. In other words, the critics allege that Marx drew conclusions that actually do not follow from his theoretical premises.[12] Once those errors are corrected, Marx's conclusion that aggregate price and profit are determined by, and equal to, aggregate value and surplus value no longer holds true. This result calls into question his theory that the exploitation of workers is the sole source of profit.[13]The inconsistency allegations have been a prominent feature of Marxian economics and the debate surrounding it since the 1970s. Andrew Kliman argues that, since internally inconsistent theories cannot possibly be right, this undermines Marx's critique of political economy and current-day research based upon it, as well as the correction of Marx's alleged inconsistencies.
Proponents of the “Temporal Single System Interpretation of Marx's value theory, like Kliman, claim that the supposed inconsistencies are actually the result of misinterpretation; they argue that when Marx's theory is understood as "temporal" and "single-system," the alleged internal inconsistencies disappear. In a recent survey of the debate, Kliman concludes that "the proofs of inconsistency are no longer defended; the entire case against Marx has been reduced to the interpretive issue.”[14]

3.0 FAILURES OF PREVENTION
At the inception of the Frankfurt School several factors endeavored to militate its development and the success of their agenda. However, instead of these factors succeeding in the achievement of their objective, they served as a springboard to the development of the school and its agenda. At this juncture, we focus our attention to these factors and also examine the various ways in which they promoted the success of the Frankfurt school.
3.1 Institute for Social Research
The earliest trace of what is presently known as the Frankfurt School is embedded in the Institute for Social Research. The institute was founded through the donation of a young Marxist Felix Weil (1898-1975) and after the success of his symposium in 1922. The institute was an adjunct of the University of Frankfurt and the first Marxist-oriented research center.[15] The purpose behind the formation of the institute for social research is to provide for studies on the labor movement and the origins of anti-Semitism which was at that time ignored in German intellectual and academic life.[16]
After the formation of the institute for social research, it was formally recognized by the ministry of education and a Marxist legal and political professor: Carl Grunberg (1923-9); was appointed the director. His contribution to the Institute was the creation of an historical archive mainly oriented to the study of the labour movement. Max Horkheimer succeeded Grunberg in 1930 and interpreted the institute’s mission to be more directed towards an interdisciplinary integration of the social sciences.
Under the leadership of Horkheimer, the institute for social research was capable to address a wide variety of economic, social, political, and aesthetic topics ranging from empirical analysis to philosophical theorization. Also, different interpretation of Marxism and its historical applications was rendered by the institute which were helpful in explaining certain hard economic themes of Karl Marx. Thus in Horkheimer’s leadership, the institute for social research objective took a radical turn which was characteristic to its future successes.
3.2 German Pre-war Context
The political tumult of Germany’s troubled interwar period greatly affected the school’s development. The failure of the working class revolution in Western Europe and the rise of Nazism in such an economically and technologically advanced nation as Germany had a great influence on thoughts of the Frankfurt school. As a result of this influence, a lot of them were faced with the task of choosing parts of Marx’s thought that might serve to clarify the contemporary social conditions that Marx himself had never seen. More so, Another key influence also came from the publication in the 1930s of Marx's Economic-Philosophical Manuscripts and The German Ideology, which showed the continuity with Hegelianism that underlay Marx's thought.
As the growing influence of National Socialism became ever more threatening, its founders decided to prepare to move the Institute out of the country.[17] Following Adolf Hitler's rise to power in 1933, the Institute left Germany for Geneva, before moving to New York City in 1935, where it became affiliated with Columbia University. Its journal was renamed to Studies in Philosophy and Social Science. It was at this moment that much of its important work began to emerge, having gained a favorable reception within American and English academia.
3.3 Employment of the Wonder Minds
Following Max Horkheimer’s assumption of leadership of the Frankfurt school (1930), the exile in America (1933) and their return to Germany (1950) makes the Frankfurt school theorists to vary. They are mostly grouped to pre-war or early theorists and post-war or later theorists. The early theorists include the persons of Max Horkheimer, Theordor Adorno, Herbert Mercuse, Friedrich Pollock, Erich Fromm, Leo Lowenthal[18] among others. While the later theorists are Jurgen Habermas, Claus Offe, Axel Honneth, and Alfred Schmidt.
Max Horkheimer (front left), Theodor Adorno (front right), and Jürgen Habermas in the background, right, in 1965 at Heidelberg.

4.0 IMPACTS OF CRITICAL THEORY
4.1 The Initiation of Critical Theory
Max Horkheimer in his Traditional and Critical theory begins by asking “what is theory?”[19]He went further to answer that in most researchers mind, theory is the sum total of propositions about a subject which are linked together in the sense that few are basic while others are derived from the basic, thus it is stored up knowledge which are descriptive.[20] More so if experience and theory contradicts each other, one of the two must be re-examined and one must be ready to change it if the weaknesses begin to show.
This conception of theory brings us to the two kinds of theory acknowledged by Horkheimer, which are Traditional Theory and Critical Theory. Traditional theory is based on scientific activity; it refers to the positivistic or purely observational mode which derives generalizations about different aspects of the world. Horkheimer argued that Traditional theory is insufficient because it is subject to a prejudice that separates theoretical activity from actual life which means that what it seeks to find is a logic that always remains true, independent of and without consideration to ongoing human activities. According to Horkheimer, the appropriate response to this dilemma is the development of a critical theory.[21]
Critical theory can be understood as a self-conscious social critique that is aimed at change and emancipation through enlightenment and that does not cling dogmatically to its own doctrinal assumptions.[22] The aim of the Frankfurt school in adopting the critical theory is to analyze the significance of the ruling understandings generated in the bourgeois society thus to interpret the areas of the society which Marx had not dealt with especially in the superstructure of society.[23] Furthermore, Horkheimer posited that critical theory is directed towards the totality of society in its historical specificity; i.e. how it is shaped at a particular point in time. Also, it is aimed at improving understanding of society by assimilating all the major social sciences such as psychology, economics, anthropology, political science, history etc. Horkheimer further posits that for a theory to be critical it must be explanatory, it must combine practical and normative thinking to explain what is wrong with current social reality, identify factors to change it and provide clear norms for criticism and practical goals for the future.[24]Therefore, whereas traditional theory can only mirror and explain reality as it presently is, critical theory's purpose is to change it; in Horkheimer's words the goal of critical theory is “the emancipation of human beings from the circumstances that enslave them”[25].
4.2 Critique of Marxian Ideology
The Frankfurt School having defined the tool (critical theory) with which they worked, went further to direct the tool towards Marxian Ideology. Nevertheless, it would be worthy to note that by using the term ‘Critique’, the Frankfurt School are explicitly linking up the critical philosophy of Immanuel Kant where the term Critique does not necessary stand as a derogative approach but as a reflection on the limits of claims made for certain kinds of knowledge. In that light, the critical theorists intended to rehabilitate Marx’s ideas through a philosophical critical approach.
The Frankfurt school theorists like Horkheimer based his work on Marxism on the epistemological base of Marx’s work which presented itself as a critique of Marx’s Capital: A Critique of Political Economy. They emphasized that Marx attempted to create a new kind of critical analysis oriented toward the unity of theory and revolutionary practice rather than a new kind of positive science. Therefore, Critique in this Marxian sense means taking the ideology of a society and critiquing it by comparing it with a posited social reality of that very society. The Frankfurt school theorists rooted their claim using the dialectical method already illustrated by Hegel and Marx.
Hegel conceived dialectics as the tendency of an idea to pass over time into its own negation as the result of conflict between its inherent contradictory aspects.[26]Hegel further posits that history evolves in a dialectical manner i.e. the present exemplifies the synthesis of past contradictions. It is an intelligible process which Hegel referred to as world spirit, which is moving towards a specific condition—the rational realization of human freedom.[27] However, Marx criticized Hegel and posited that it is not consciousness of men that determine their being but on their social standing that determine that consciousness.[28] Therefore, Marx theory constitute of a scenario where capitalism is replaced by communism.
However, the critical theorists adopted a self-correcting method i.e. a dialectical method that would enable them to correct previous false dialectical interpretations. Hence, the critical theorists rejected the historicism, material tensions and class struggle of Marx. The critical theorist in rejecting these views emasculates the revolutionary potential within western societies which is an indication that Marx’s dialectical interpretation and prediction were either incomplete or incorrect.    
4.3 Critique of Western Civilization
Two works of the philosophers of the school of Frankfurt are notable for the critique of Western Civilization; Dialectic of Enlightenment and Minima Moralia by Max Horkheimer and Theodore Adorno, both written while they were in exile, escaping Nazism. They criticised Western Civilization by exposing the failures of the “age of enlightenment” (if it could truly be called so). The opening words of the first chapter of the Dialectic of Enlightenment states: “Enlightenment, understood in the wildest sense as the advance of thought, has always aimed at liberating human beings from fear and installing them as masters. Yet the wholly enlightened earth is radiant with triumphant calamity.”[29] The above statement is a show that the hope of the age of enlightenment has excessively crumbled. The rationality of Western Civilization seems to be an amalgam of domination and technological rationality, bringing all of external and internal nature under the power of the human subject. But in the process, man loses himself entirely, so much so that he is unable to retrace his steps. Evidently, the Dialectics states that “on the way towards modern science human beings have discarded meaning.”[30] And again, that “the enlightenment has eradicated the last remnant of its own self-awareness.
Human beings through the acclaimed civilization of the West has only sort to learn how to control and dominate both nature and human beings, and the result of this has evidently been catastrophic, it did not just lead to the European fascism, it also led to a succession of wars. It says again at the conclusion of the first chapter that “enlightenment is turning itself into an outright deception of the masses.
In the Minima Moralia, Theodor Adorno explains that Western Civilization has been destructive to humanity, even though it has come as hope-offering, hence the title of the book, Reflections from Damaged life. Adorno wrote this book during the World War II, and in his introduction he wrote, “the sorrowful science” which is a way of relating it to Fredrick Nietzsche’s Gay Science. The book is concerned about teaching good life, a central theme of both the Greek and Hebrew sources of Western philosophy. Adorno holds that a good honest life is no longer possible, because we live in an inhuman society. Thus, the book opens with the statement, “Life does not live.”[31] In a series of short reflections and aphorisms, Adorno considers the subversive nature of toys, the desolation of the family, the ungenuinness of being genuine, the decay of conversation, the rise of occultism and the history of tact. He shows how the smallest changes in the everyday behaviour stand in relation to the most catastrophic events of the twentieth century.[32]
Against Western Civilization, Adorno has this to say in the Minima Moralia “there is no true life in a false life.” In one of his reflections, titled “How nice of you, Doctor,” Adorno exposes the fact that modernity who served as a doctor, prescribing against the Christian age has suggested a wrong prescription. Thus, Adorno wrote: “there is nothing innocuous left, the little pleasures, expressions of life seemed exempt from the responsibility of thought, not only have an element of defiant silliness, of callous refusal to see, but directly serve diametrical opposite.”[33] Adorno grieves the irretrievable loss of a paradise of a privileged childhood, holding fast to the Judeao-Christian-Enlightenment vision of redemption, which he calls the only valid viewpoint with which to engage a deeply trouble world. Affirming that this would necessarily imply a surrender of modernity, he asserts that in many people, it is already an impertinence to say “I.”



5.0 PROVIDENTIAL EXILE IN AMERICA

5.1 ESCAPING NAZISM
How the fathers of Critical Theory found their way to America came as a result of Hitler’s intellectual viewpoint which was influenced during his youth not only by these currents in the German tradition but also by specific Austrian movements that professed various political sentiments, notably those of pan-Germanic expansionism and anti-Semitism. This intellectual preparation would probably not have been sufficient for the growth of National Socialism in Germany, but for that country’s defeat in World War 1. The defeat and the resulting disillusionment, pauperization, and frustration particularly among the lower middle classes, paved the way for the success of the propaganda of Hitler and the Nazis[34].
The treaty of Versailles (1919), the formal settlement of World War I drafted without German participation, alienated many Germans with its imposition of harsh monetary and territorial reparations.[35] The significant resentment expressed toward the peace treaty gave Hitler a starting point. Because German representatives (branded the “November criminals” by National Socialists) agreed to cease hostilities and did not unconditionally surrender in the armistice of November 11, 1918, there was a widespread feeling particularly in the military that Germany’s defeat had been orchestrated by diplomats at the Versailles meetings[36].
From the beginning, Hitler’s propaganda of revenge for this “traitorous” act, through which the German people had been “stabbed in the back,” and his call for rearmament had strong appeal within military circles, which regarded the peace only as a temporary setback in Germany’s expansionist program. The ruinous inflation of the German currency in 1923 wiped out the savings of many middle-class households and led to further public alienation and dissatisfaction. It was in the light of all these that the propaganda of Hitler paves way for him to rise into power. The underside of its propaganda machine was its apparatus of terror, horror, and error, with its ubiquitous secret police and concentration camps. Between 1938 and 1945 Hitler’s regime attempted to expand and apply the Nazi system to territories outside the German Reich. This endeavor was confined, in 1938, to lands inhabited by German-speaking populations, but in 1939 Germany was to subjugate non-German-speaking nationalities as well. Germany’s invasion of Poland on September 1, which initiated World War 11, was the logical outcome of Hitler’s plan.[37]
Furthermore, Hitler’s rise to power, with His ferocious nationalism, his contempt of the Slavs, and his hatred of the Jews whom he identified with a kind of cosmic evil. This eventually led to the transit lift of the fathers of Critical Theory, as they found their way to America on exile. According to him, the Jews were to be discriminated against in the society not according to their religion but according to their race. Another reason the Institute had to leave Frankfurt in the first place was that, in addition to being radicals and Marxists, the members of the group were almost all Jewish.[38] The school was created by Herman Weil, a German Jew who had made a fortune importing grain from Argentina, and his son Felix, who like many young men was radicalized after Germany’s defeat in World War I.            
Among the tidal wave of academic refugees from Hitler’s Germany, the members of the Institute were actually very lucky to have escaped the horror attack of Hitler. For a brief period the school was in Geneva, but later relocated to Morningside Heights, where it formed an uneasy partnership with Columbia University.[39] Max Horkheimer, with a prescience that was all too rare among German Jews, had already shifted the Institute’s endowment out of German banks and shipped its library out of the country.[40] The scholars reassembled in Geneva, but this could only be a temporary respite, since most of them could not get permanent Swiss visas. As Wheatland shows in the first of the book’s four sections, Horkheimer embarked on a well-thought-out campaign to find a new home for the Institute in the United States, sending out a pamphlet with testimonials to sociology departments at American universities.[41]
It would be hard to overstate the importance of the Frankfurt School in recent American thought. Philosophers, psychologists, and sociologists like Theodor Adorno, Walter Benjamin, Herbert Marcuse, Erich Fromm, and Max Horkheimer to name just the best-known members of the group helped to develop a subtle and powerful way of thinking about the problems of modern society. Critical Theory, as it is usually capitalized, adapted the revolutionary impulse of Marxism to 20th century conditions, in which mass culture and totalitarianism seemed to shut off any real possibility of social transformation.[42]
5.2 FERTILITY OF THE PROJECT
Having gone through the above subheadings, it should be noted that “the Frankfurt School is a complex phenomenon and the style of social thought which has come to be principally associated with it –Critical Theory- which has been expounded and interpreted in a variety of ways.”[43] The achievement of this heading “fertility of the project” was a collaborative and collective responsibility of the management of this school, which include Horkheimer, Adorno, Marcuse, Pollock and so on. They were able to achieve this through their collective tireless effort, contributing their ideas and quota. The fertility of the project which could equally be described as the fertility of the school of Frankfurt, talks about the impact of the managements toward making the school what it is.[44] 
The Frankfurt school thinkers were led by their pessimism into a retreat from Marxian social theory and then towards an essentially philosophical and Neo-Hegelian critique of ideology”.  Nevertheless, Horkheimer, Adorno and Marcuse were responsible for the theory of capitalist society which emphasized its cultural manifestations above all other aspects. Being trapped in the climate of cultural loss and decline which must be linked to their experience of the rise of fascism in Germany, the ‘critical theory’ developed by these men during this period was overwhelmingly concerned with the mounting irrationality of social and cultural values and their reflection in the ideas of positivism and scientism.
Indeed, it is of some significance that there has been such widespread interest in the ideas of the principal Frankfurt school theorists, for their work vividly struck a chord when philosophical interpretations of Marxist concepts were at the height of their popularity. This showed the interest of the school over their work to search for a better world after 1968 in the English speaking world. That is they made a “promise of an intellectualized and culturally sophisticated quasi-Marxism had undeniably appealed”[45].
Although this school became entangled with the idea of philosophy, which was reinforced by both Marcuse and Adorno, “at the same time the school developed a strong interest in the psychoanalysis and this remained a prominent element in its later work”[46]. It is equally good to state that the management while in exile were able to elaborate as well as systematize their theoretical views which enabled them to shape and organize a distinctive school of thought. “By the time this school returned to Frankfurt in 1950, the principal ideas of critical theory had been clearly set out in a number of major writings and the Frankfurt school began to exert an important influence upon German social thought.”[47]
It will not be out of place to reveal Horkheimer’s original formulation of critical theory, first, that his hesitant and somewhat skeptical evaluation of the role of the working class, already gave an intimation of his later profound pessimism about the existence of any real emancipatory force in modern society. Secondly, that the political significance which he attributed to the work of critical intellectuals was a reversion to the pre-Marxian conception of the processes of social change, closely resembling the outlook of the young Hegelian and critical critics.”[48] The overriding concern of the Frankfurt school with cultural phenomena -that is with the manifestation and product of human consciousness. This also involved a particular interest in the individual as a center of thought and action and in psychology, especially in the form of psychoanalysis.”[49]
Also, Horkheimer, on becoming the director of the Institute launched an empirical study of workers’ attitude in Germany.”[50] In exile also the question of the relation between critical theory and empirical research emerged in a more acute form, for the development of a distinctive school of social theory, hostile to positivism/empiricism, took place in an environment in which the social sciences were oriented primarily to empirical investigation.”[51]
5.3 The Birth of Analytic Philosophy
Every human being is afforded with an accessible opportunity to participate in the system of commonly held philosophical beliefs and doctrines; which is widely held to be an offshoot of a defined or given tradition. The general history of philosophy that falls under the context of time (around the nineteenth and twentieth century), is a direct indicative of what can be relatively attributed to the origins of “Analytic Philosophy.”[52] As to what line of account and description that can be given to this sort of philosophical tradition, the analytic philosophy can be said to be a particular variant of philosophical tradition within the domains of western thought.[53]
Resulting from the question of method and in an attempt to give an explanation of the confrontation of analytic philosophy with the traditional conceptions of philosophy; there is also a need to give a detailed description of what the principle of analytic philosophy entails and its inception into the panorama of contemporary systems of philosophical thoughts and beliefs. Analytic philosophy is a philosophical school that submits to the view that language (which is primarily concerned with the scientific communicative method of proposition and meaning) is the basic and core foundation of other subjects of thoughts and human reasoning.[54] They are subjected to the position which affirms the analysis of the structure of thought; which can only be ascertained when all that concerns linguistic schemes, structures, and methods, are critically analyzed.[55]
Indisputably, the penetration of analytic philosophy within the better parts of the nineteenth and twentieth century, left marks of its domination and influence in the academic terrains of the philosophical dimensions of America, Britain, and Europe. Of course, it is of no insignificant telling that this philosophical school was perceived to be the ideal and most reliable methodic approach; in the quest for clarification of meaning and proposition. Therefore, the goal of analytic philosophy is to discover what is true, rather than making provisions of methodic explanations for living one’s life.[56]
Essentially, there was a dramatic shift in the enterprise of philosophy. One tends to see the radical twist and backdrop from “absolute idealism” which was a major and influential philosophical movement before the advent of the analytic philosophy. The activities of the analytic school became initiated by two major figures in the circle of contemporary philosophy. These two philosophers- Bertrand Russell and G. E. Moore- were both contemporaries of the twentieth century.
It is recorded that this period was characterized by the uprising of the systematic revolution; that uncompromising breakaway from the doctrine of the Hegelian philosophical doctrine and system.[57] The Hegelian philosophical system had most of its constituent on the model of idealism; a subset of “metaphysical monism,” with the notion that: “The world and all that concerns its entities or objects are nothing but illusions. As such, the very nature of the universe is unreal, mentally or spiritually based, rather than materially composed. Philosophers who were part of the school include: F. H. Bradley, Bernard Bosanquet, and J. E. Mc Taggart.[58]
In reaction to these shades of positions by the idealist, both Moore and Russell gave their distinct views and postulations. Moore posited a synthetic tool which helped in the analyzing languages with its meaning and propositions. This led to the clarification of language to their ordinary forms, as it fits suitably with the “common sense” view of the world. Russell on the other hand, saw metaphysical language as loose and obscure; heavily pregnant with ambiguities and nonsensical ideas. Hence, he recommended the principle of “logical atomism,” which subjected every form of language to the domain of linguistic analysis; were facts were rigourously examined for the invention of a new language. It is worth mentioning, that the only criterion for the new language to be considered as valid, necessarily needs to be in absolute correspondence to the facts. This shows that philosophy is deeply concerned with the task of clarification other than discovery; and the unending pursuit of meaning rather truth.[59]
Another outlook relatively linked with the analytical philosophy invasion, is the philosophical insights of Ludwig Wittgenstein; of all of which were reflected through the volumes of his ideas in one of his basic writings: “Tractatus Logico Philosophicus.” This piece of writing came into the break of recognition in the year 1919. Wittgenstein’s philosophical analysis is characterized by the logical assumption that language contains a “logical skeleton” whose sole function is- “to state facts.” He based this argument on the exercise of his thought other than “observation.”[60]
More seriously, he assumed that all languages are strikingly similar, despite their superficial differences. Although he later discovered a flaw in his analogy, by saying that the only way one should analyze language is by a careful observation of its usage and operations, not by mere thinking (which is a product of logical atomism). Hence, he shifted the pattern of analysis which was engrossed in logic and the “construction of a perfect language.”[61]
The reverse became the case. Wittgenstein liberated himself from the thought patterns of Russell, conforming himself to the postulations of Moore. This made him give in to the “analysis of ordinary language” whose facts can be clarified and actualized by its conformity with the “criterion of common sense.” This made him see language as a form of life rather than a single pattern alone. Consequently, the business of philosophical analysis should be solely concerned with a careful description of language, than its definition and explanations.[62]





6.0 CONCLUSION
The necessary requirement for the even balance and equilibrium of the social and economic structure of the society, have undergone different stages of transition through the infiltration of the critical tool of analysis. Spurred by the need to create a unique assessment of universe in midst of its social, economic and political constrains, the School of Frankfurt developed and formulated the Critical Theory. This tool served as a liberating force of revolution and analytical criticism against the then uprising crisis of the Marxian socio-economic and political ideology.
Ostensibly, the volumes of these shades of ideas represented in this piece of writing have shed insightful lines of manifestations on what contemporary philosophy should rightly entail. In this paper all the points of the table of contents have been highlighted, which fulfills the responsibility of exposing the philosophical literature of the School of Frankfurt and the Critical Theory.


BIBLIOGRAPHY
                                          
Adorno, Theodor. Minima Moralia: Reflections on a Damaged Life (ed.) E.F.N. Jephcott. New York: Verso Publishers, 2005.
Bottomore, Tom. The Frankfurt School and Its Critics. New York: Routledge, 1989.
Carver, Terrell Marx and Marxism, United Kingdom: Manchester University Press, 1991.
Corradetti, Claudio. The Frankfurt School and Critical Theory. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Originally published: October 21, 2011.
Campbell, M. Heather. The Britannica Guide to Political and Social Movements that Changed The Modern World. New York: Britannica Educational Publishing, 2010.
Dubiel, Helmut. The Origins of Critical Theory: An Interview With Leo Lowenthal. By in Telos. Telos Press Publishing 1968.
D. Rasmussen. Critical Theory and Philosophy. In Rasmussen, D. (ed.), The Handbook of Critical Theory, Oxford: Blackwell, 1999.
Dummett, Michael. Origins of Analytical Philosophy. New York: Bloomsbury Publishing Plc, 2014.
Dmitriev, V.K. Economic Essays on Value, Competition and Utility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1974.
Glock, Hans-Johann. What Is Analytic Philosophy? New York: Cambridge University Press, 2008.
Howard, M.C. and King, J.E. A History of Marxian Economics. Volume II, Chapter 12, Section III, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1992.
Horkheimer, Max. Traditional and Critical Theory, trans. by Matthew J. O’Connell and Others. New York: The Continuum Publishing Company, 1972.
Horkheimer, Max & Adorno, Theodor Dialectic of enlightenment ed. Gunzelin Schmid Noerr, trans. Edmund Jephcott).  California: Stanford University Press, 2002.
Jay, Martin. The Dialectical Imagination. A History of the Frankfurt School and the Institute of Social Research 1923–1950. London: Heinemann, 1973.
J. Bohman. Critical Theory and Democracy. In: Rasmussen, D. (ed.), The Handbook of Critical Theory. Oxford: Blackwell, 1996.
Jacobs, Jack. Frankfurt School, Jewish Lives, and Antisemitism. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2015.
Haugen, Brenda. Adolf Hitler Dictator of Nazi Germany. New York: Compass Point Books, 2006.
Kliman, Andrrew. Reclaiming Marx's Capital. Maryland: Lexington Books, 2007.
Kuhn, Rick.  Henryk Grossman and the Recovery of Marxism. Urbana and Chicago: University of Illinois Press, 2007.
Marx, Karl. Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts in Collected Works, Vol.3, London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1975.
Marx, Karl. Preface to A Contribution to Critique of Political Economy in Collected Works, Vol. 29, London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1975.
Marx, Karl. Capital: A Critique of Political Economy. Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1986.
Weatland, Thomas. The Frankfurt School in Exile. London: University of Minnesota Press, 2009.
Preston, Aaron. Analytic Philosophy: The History of An Illusion. New York: Continuum International Publishing Group, 2010.
Raymond, Guess. The Idea of A Critical Theory: Habermas and the Frankfurt School. Cambridge University Press, 1981.
Searle, John. Contemporary Philosophy in the United States, in N. Bunnin and E. P. Tsui-James (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy, 2nd ed., Massachusetts: Blackwell Publishing, Inc., 2003.
Stumpf, Enoch Samuel. Philosophy: History and Problems. New York: McGraw Hill, Inc., 1997.
Wiggershaus, Rolf. The Frankfurt School: Its History, Theories, and Political Significance. trans. Michael Robertson. Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1994.




CONSULTED ONLINE SOURCES











[1] Cf. Rolf Wiggershaus, The Frankfurt School: Its History, Theories, and Political Significance. trans. Michael Robertson (Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1994), p. 1-2.
[2] Cf. Wiggershaus, The Frankfurt School: Its History, Theories, and Political Significance. p. 2-4.
[3] Cf. Wiggershaus, The Frankfurt School: Its History, Theories, and Political Significance. p. 4-5.
[4] http://www.allaboutphilosophy.org/what-is-marxism-faq.htm
[5] http://www.allaboutphilosophy.org/what-is-marxism-faq.htm
[6] Terrell Carver, Marx and Marxism, (United Kingdom: Manchester University Press, 1991) p. 185.
[7] Terrell Carver, Marx and Marxism, (United Kingdom: Manchester University Press, 1991) p. 185.

[8] Terrell Carver, Marx and Marxism, (United Kingdom: Manchester University Press, 1991) p. 187.
[9]Cf. Karl Marx, Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts in Collected Works, Vol.3, (London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1975), pp. 302-304.
[10] Cf. Karl Marx, Preface to A Contribution to Critique of Political Economy in Collected Works, Vol. 29, (London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1975), pp. 261-265.
[11] Cf. Terrell Carver, Marx and Marxism, (United Kingdom: Manchester University Press, 1991) p. 187.
[12]Cf. V. K. Dmitriev, Economic Essays on Value, Competition and Utility. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1974), p. 45.
[13] M.C. Howard and J. E. King, A History of Marxian Economics: Volume II, Chapter 12, Section III, (USA: Princeton University Press, 1992), p. 26.
[14] Andrew Kliman, Reclaiming Marx's "Capital", (Maryland: Lexington Books) p. 208.
[16] Claudio Corradetti ,The Frankfurt School and Critical Theory, Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Originally published: October 21, 2011).
[17]Cf. The Origins of Critical Theory: An interview with Leo Lowenthal by Helmut Dubiel  (Telos Press Publishing, 1968), p. 25.
[18] Cf. RickKuhn, Henryk Grossman and the Recovery of Marxism (Chicago: University of Illinois Press, 2007), p. 14.

[19] Max Horkheimer, Traditional and Critical Theory, trans. by Matthew J. O’Connell and others (New York: The Continuum Publishing Company, 1972) p. 188
[20]ibid
[21]Rasmussen, D., Critical Theory and Philosophy In Rasmussen, D. (ed.), The Handbook of Critical Theory, (Oxford: Blackwell, 1996), p .18
[22]Geuss, Raymond (1981). The Idea of A Critical Theory: Habermas and The Frankfurt School. Cambridge University Press, p. 58
[23]Martin Jay, The Dialectical Imagination: A History of the Frankfurt School and the Institute of Social Research 1923–1950. (London: Heinemann, 1973,) p. 21.
[24]Bohman, J. "Critical Theory and Democracy" In: Rasmussen, D. (ed.), The Handbook of Critical Theory, (Oxford: Blackwell, 1996), p. 190.
[25]Max Horkheimer, Traditional and Critical Theory, trans. by Matthew J. O’Connell and others (New York: The Continuum Publishing Company, 1972), p. 219.
[28]Cf. Karl Marx, Capital: A Critique of Political Economy (Progress Publishers, Moscow, 1986), p. 45. preface
[29] Max Horkheimer & Theodor Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment.  trans. Edmund Jephcott  (California: Stanford University Press, 2002), p. 1.
[30] Max Horkheimer & Theodor Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment, p. 3.
[31] Theodor Adorno, Minima Moralia: Reflections on a Damaged Life (ed.),  E.F.N. Jephcott (New York: Verso Publishers, 2005), p. i.
[32] https//en.m.wikipedia.org/wiki/Minima_Moralia
[33] Theodor Adorno, Minima Moralia: Reflections on a Damaged Life. p. 25.
[34]  Cf. Brenda Haugen, Adolf Hitler Dictator of Nazi Germany (New York: Compass point Books, 2006), P. 56.
[35]  Heather M. Campbell, the Britannica Guide to Political and Social Movements that Changed the Modern World (New York: Britannica Educational Publishing, 2010), P. 207.
[36] Heather M. Campbell, the Britannica Guide to Political and Social Movements that Changed the Modern World, p. 207.
[37]   Heather M. Campbell, the Britannica Guide to Political and Social Movements that Changed the Modern World (New York: Britannica Educational Publishing, 2010), P. 212.
[38]  Cf. Jack Jacobs, Frankfurt School, Jewish Lives, and Antisemitism (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2015),P. 45.
[39]  Cf. Thomas Weatland, the Frankfurt School in Exile (London: University of Minnesota Press, 2009), P. 35.
[40]  Cf. Jack Jacobs, Frankfurt School, Jewish Lives, and Antisemitism, P. 44.
[41]  Cf. Thomas Weatland, The Frankfurt School in Exile, P. 35.
[42]  Cf. Thomas Weatland, The Frankfurt School in Exile, p. 61.
[43] Cf. Tom Bottomore, The Frankfurt School and Its Critics (New York: Routledge, 2002), p. 11.
[44] Cf. Bottomore, The Frankfurt School and Its Critics, p. 8.
[45] Tom Bottomore, The Frankfurt School and Its Critics (New York: Routledge, 2002), p. 8.
[46] Tom Bottomore, The Frankfurt School and Its Critics, p. 13.
[47] Tom Bottomore, The Frankfurt School and Its Critics, p. 13.
[48] Tom Bottomore, The Frankfurt School and Its Critics, p. 17.
[49] Tom Bottomore, The Frankfurt School and Its Critics, p. 19.
[50] Tom Bottomore, The Frankfurt School and Its Critics, p. 22.
[51] Tom Bottomore, The Frankfurt School and Its Critics (New York: Routledge, 1989), p.22.
[52] Cf. Michael Dummett, Origins of Analytical Philosophy (New York: Bloomsbury Publishing Plc, 2014), p. 1.
[53] Cf. John Searle, Contemporary Philosophy in the United States, in N. Bunnin and E. P. Tsui-James (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy, 2nd ed., (Massachusetts: Blackwell Publishing, Inc., 2003), p. 1.
[54] Cf. Hans-Johann Glock, What is Analytic Philosophy? (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2008), p. 122.
[55] Cf. Glock, What is Analytic Philosophy?  p. 122.
[56] Cf. Aaron Preston, Analytic Philosophy: The History of An Illusion (New York: Continuum International Publishing Group, 2010), p. 7-11.
[57] Cf. Samuel Enoch Stumpf, Philosophy: History and Problems (New York: McGraw Hill, Inc., 1997), p. 447.
[58] Cf. Stumpf, Philosophy: History and Problems. p. 447.
[59] Cf. Samuel Enoch Stumpf, Philosophy: History and Problems (New York: McGraw Hill, Inc., 1997), p. 448.
[60] Cf. Stumpf, Philosophy: History and Problems. p. 461.
[61] Cf. Stumpf, Philosophy: History and Problems.  p. 463.
[62] Cf. Stumpf, Philosophy: History and Problems.  p. 463.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

SUMMARY OF PROVIDENTISSIMUS DEUS, ENCYCLICAL LETTER OF POPE LEO XIII ON THE STUDY OF THE HOLY SCRIPTURE.

summary and appraisal of chapters one, two and three of the book The African Origin of Greek Philosophy: An Exercise in Afrocentrism, by Innocent C. Onyewuenyi.

THE LAST THREE WAYS TO PROVES GOD'S EXISTENCE BY THOMAS AQUINAS