SUMMARY OF EPISTEMOLOGY
SUMMARY OF EPISTEMOLOGY
Note: check my yr1
note on intro. To Phil. To get the meaning of epistemology and types of
knowledge.
NOTE: always
support your work with some proponents of any school of thought. Always
evaluate your work by showing the strengths and weaknesses of any school of
thought. Precision is highly recommended.
1.
Is
justified true believe knowledge? (Elmond Gettier problem)
Is
knowledge the same as opinion, judgement, persuasion and belief even if they
eventually turn out to be true? In his books, Meno and Theatetus Plato
considers all these and dismisses them as inadequate characteristics of
knowledge. In epistemology, the traditional requisite for knowledge is
justified true belief. This implies that for one to claim that one knows
something, one ought to believe in it, and this belief ought to be true and
justified. However, In the year 1963, an article, Is Justified True Belief
Knowledge?, was published by Edmund L. Gettier in a bid to demonstrate that the
three conditions, posited by traditional epistemologist are not sufficient conditions
for knowledge. He noted these two points: first, that it is possible for a
person to be justified in believing a proposition that is in fact false,
following the same conditions stipulated traditionally. Second, he proffered a
possible solution that for any proposition P, if S is justified in believing P,
and P entails Q, and S deduces Q from P and accepts Q as a result of this
deduction, then S is justified in believing Q.
Gettier’s
refutation has received several reactions both positive and negative. To be
justified in holding a belief means to have evidence for the belief. Where the
evidence in question is not conclusive, the belief could turn out to be false. A
man acquires a time belief as to the time of day, but cannot be said to have
knowledge. But even if it turns out to be true, it still does not qualify to be
knowledge, because his evidence is not conclusive. The belief just happens by
chance to be true. For instance, according to Bertrand
Russell, someone may look at a clock which is not going, though he thinks it is, and who happens to look at it at the moment when it is right. From the different attempt made by epistemologists like A.J. Ayer, Roderich Chisholm and Drehea, it is obvious that the problem in the traditional definition or analysis of knowledge as “Justified true belief” hinges on the word “justified”. How is belief justified? Or what is the necessary and sufficient condition for justification of any knowledge claim? Is it when it has ‘good evidence’ as claimed by Drehea? Is it when one’s belief is acceptable or reasonable as claimed by Roderich Chisholm? Is it when one he is sure as claimed by A. J. Ayer? Or is it when one has conclusive evidence? Certainty is one of the conditions of knowledge. Before a person can claim to know anything, it must be sure that that thing is really the case. That is why opinion is not knowledge for it involves uncertainty and instability. Consequently, belief is not the same as knowledge because knowledge must be based on conclusive evidence and certainty. Belief is however not based on conclusive evidence, but on inconclusive evidence or on assumption. If I read in the News Papers, for example, that somebody has died I cannot say that I know that the person has died. I can only say that I believe that he has died because the evidence I have for it is the News Paper report. I am only assuming that the Newspaper report is true. However, it could be false. Therefore, my evidence is inconclusive.
Russell, someone may look at a clock which is not going, though he thinks it is, and who happens to look at it at the moment when it is right. From the different attempt made by epistemologists like A.J. Ayer, Roderich Chisholm and Drehea, it is obvious that the problem in the traditional definition or analysis of knowledge as “Justified true belief” hinges on the word “justified”. How is belief justified? Or what is the necessary and sufficient condition for justification of any knowledge claim? Is it when it has ‘good evidence’ as claimed by Drehea? Is it when one’s belief is acceptable or reasonable as claimed by Roderich Chisholm? Is it when one he is sure as claimed by A. J. Ayer? Or is it when one has conclusive evidence? Certainty is one of the conditions of knowledge. Before a person can claim to know anything, it must be sure that that thing is really the case. That is why opinion is not knowledge for it involves uncertainty and instability. Consequently, belief is not the same as knowledge because knowledge must be based on conclusive evidence and certainty. Belief is however not based on conclusive evidence, but on inconclusive evidence or on assumption. If I read in the News Papers, for example, that somebody has died I cannot say that I know that the person has died. I can only say that I believe that he has died because the evidence I have for it is the News Paper report. I am only assuming that the Newspaper report is true. However, it could be false. Therefore, my evidence is inconclusive.
However,
knowledge involves belief in the sense that a person cannot say that he knows
something but that he does not believe it. ‘I know it but I don’t believe it’
“I know that I am a living being, but I don’t believe it”. These are absurd and
self contradictory. If you know something then you cannot say you don’t believe
it. This is because knowledge implies certainty, and nobody can refuse to
believe what he knows to be certain. But it makes sense to say, “I don’t know
it, but I believe it”, “I don’t know what tomorrow will turn out to be, but I
believe in it”. Finally, belief can pass into knowledge when justified. Thus
the traditional characterisation of knowledge as justified true belief still
stands in spite of Gettier’s contention. His examples in support of his
contention are those of inconclusive evidences.
2.
Write
short note on the following kinds of knowledge:
i.
Empirical
knowledge: it is the knowledge acquired through sense-perception, that is ,
through any of the five senses. It is knowledge of an individual object, a
particular object, not knowledge of a class or category of objects. This is
because the sense organs can only present us with particular concrete objects.
There are three things involved in the act of sensation: the object perceived
which is material, the sense-organ with which it is perceived, and the subject
that interprets what is perceived and gives it a meaning. The senses in
themselves cannot give maning to the objects of sense-perception without
reason. Again, senses can be influenced by our habit, our environment,
prejudices, emotions, prior conceptions etc. it is pertinent to note that for a
proper perception of things, the subject’s psychological and physiological
conditions must be in order.
ii.
Inferential
knowledge: it is the type of knowledge that is acquired by inference. It could
be immediate inference or mediate. Whereas in immideiate inference implications
are drawn from what is said, e.g. to say that a lady is a spinster is to imply
that she is not married; in mediate inference a conclusion is drawn from a set
of premises in the form of syllogism:
All
human beings are mortal
All
Nigerians are human beings
Therefore,
all Nigerians are mortal
Inferential
knowledge can be by demonstration or by argumentation. While demonstration
moves from given premises to a conclusion, in argumentation there is first a
conclusion and second the justification of the conclusion. It can also be by
deduction or induction. Whereas deduction draws particular conclusion from
general principles, induction draws general principles from particular cases.
Induction is the method of modern science.
iii.
Intuitive
knowledge: it is knowledge gained by intuition. It is knowledge acquired
diriectly by an immediate contact of the mind with the object without going
through the process of reasoning. It comes as a flash into the mind. It occur
in different forms: first, empirical internal intuition, that is, through
introspection and reflection by which we become aware of what is going on in
us, e.g. that we are becoming angry, tired, feeling happy etc. second, emotional
intuition e.g when were feel that something bad or good well occur without its
rationale. Third, inventive intuition which has to do with having intuitive
vision. Fourth, intuitive knowledge can also come in the form of innate ideas.
Fifth, it can come in the form of the intuition of being, as in the case of
metaphysicians. Finally, it occurs in the form of mystical intuition, as in the
case of mystics. In intuitive knowledge, we do not prove or even acquire what
we know, we simply discover it without labouring for it or reasoning about it.
It comes simply and suddenly as an insight uneexpectly.
iv.
A
posteriori knowledge: it is the knowledge that is gained through empirical
experience. It is the knowledge acquired by means of the senses. It is
important to note that reason is needed for the right judgment of the sense
experience. When a blind man touches something, the sense of touch does not
tell him what he is touching. It is his reason that interprets his experience
and tells him what he is touching. So the senses alone, without reason cannot
furnish us with knowledge.
v.
Synthetic
knowledge: see synthetic a priori knowledge
vi.
A
priori knowledge: it is the knowledge
acquired prior to experience and independently of experience. Hence, it is the
knowledge that is acquired by reason without experience. That is the argument
of the rationalists. They reject empiricism by positing that there is a kind of
knowledge that is acquired without experience. Example of such proponents are
Plato, John Scotus, Spinoza, Leibnitz, Hegel.
vii.
Analytic
knowledge: see synthetic a priori knowledge
viii.
Synthetic
a priori knowledge: it is knowledge that is both a priori and synthetic as
well. This was Kant’s contribution to epistemology. Prior to Kant, it was
generally believed by philosophers that only analytic propositions could be a
priori, while a synthetic proposition was always a posterior. Analytic
proposition is a proposition in which what is affirmed in the predicate is
already contained in the subject. Hence, the predicate adds nothing to what is
already contained in the subject, and so knowledge is not increased. For
instance, if I tell you that a bachelor is an unmarried man, what information
am I giving you? Hence, analytic propositions are tautological. On the
contrary, synthetic proposition is a proposition I which the predicate adds
something new to the subject. What the predicate affirms, in other words, is
not contained in the subject so it adds something new to it and gives information. For instance, if I
tell you that I am a Nigerian, and that I am a professor of philosophy. I have
given you information. Since the fact of being a Nigerian does not imply being
a professor of philosophy, the predicate adds something new to the subject, the
proposition gives information. Whereas, an analytic proposition is necessarily
true and cannot be denied without self contradiction, a synthetic proposition
is not necessarily true and it can be denied without self-contradiction. It may
be true or false. Before Kant, it was generally believed that a proposition
could not be both a priori and synthetic at the same time. Kant debunk this
view by positing synthetic a priori propositions. He argues that in Ethics,
Mathematics and Physics, propositions like, “The moral law obliges man to
perform his duty” “2 + 3=5)” “every event has a cause” are synthetic a priori
propositions. They are prior to experience, yet they are not tautological. They
are, on the contrary, synthetic. They cannot be contradicted by experience,
they are not derived from experience, yet they give information. In his
“Copernican Revolution”, Kant shows how synthetic a priori is possible. During
his time, the common belief was that in the process of acquiring knowledge,
objects imposed themselves on the human mind which passively received them.
Kant rejected and reversed the view by positing that it is the mind that
imposed itself, its own structure, on objects, and makes them conform to it. It
makes objects appear to us according to this structure. This imply that we do
not know things in themselves (noumena) but the way they appear to us
(phenomena). And the way they appear to
us is the way our mind makes them appear to us. The implication of this is that
knowledge( of the phenomena ) is subjective and relative. If this is the case,
then his theory is neutral; it is neither true nor false. It is what the mind
makes out of it is what is true for that individual.
ix.
Conceptual
knowledge: it is the knowledge in terms of universal concepts, acquired through
the process of abstraction; hence it is also known as abstract or intellectual
knowledge. Abstraction is the process whereby abstract ideas (universal
concepts) are abstracted from particular concrete objects. This is what Edmund
Husserl calls “eidetic reduction” in his phenomenology, a process whereby the
particular traits, individual characteristics, of an object are set aside in
order to get at the essence of the object. The mind plays the major role in
Abstraction through the process of separation. The mind analyses and
synthesises what is particular so as to get the general- that which cut across
all the differences in a class of a thing that makes them what they are, the
essence. For instance, despites the differences that exist among human being-
height, weight, colour, size, sexes, etc., it is the universal idea or concept
of man that is our unifying factor. Same is applicable to other things like
trees, houses, cars etc. however, the pertinent question is, what is the
ontological status of the universals? Are they entities? Are they physical or
non-physical? For instance in man, what is the essence of man. Is it something
that can be pin point or not? This is the problem with this kind of knowledge. Basically, there are three positions that proffered solution
to this problem. One is Ultra-realism or exaggerated realism that admits
that essence or universals are real ontological entities existing on their own
as immaterial entities independently of material things. its proponents include
Plato, John Scotus Eriugena, St Anselm. Two is moderate realism or
conceptualism that affirm the universals as being real but not as separate
entities existing on their own independently of individual things. Rather they
exist in individual things from which the mind abstracts (extracts) them and
forms them into concepts. Thus the universals exist as concepts in the mind but
with objective foundation in things. its exponents include Aristotle, St.
Thomas Aquinas and Boethius. Three is nominalism that denies the existence of
essences or universals by arguing that universals are nothing but mere names
designating similarities between things. nominalists include Roscellinus,
William of Ockham. From the foregoing, it appears that the moderate realism is
more tenable than the other extremes. Because as Aristotle would say in his
Metaphysics, that there are tow ways of knowing things. first, as particulars,
we may know them as individual things as we perceive them. second, as
universals, we may also know things, not exactly as we perceive them with the
senses, but conceptually in terms of their universal nature or essences. This
is conceptual knowledge.
x.
Self-knowledge
and the knowledge of others: this is knowledge of self awareness, the awareness
of one’s existence which every conscious man has. It is the foundation for the
awareness of other things. for nobody can be conscious or aware of anything
without being conscious at the same time of his or her own existence.
Self-awareness is spontaneous, intuitive and indubitable. The knowledge of
others is however, not intuitive like self-awareness. George Berkeley argues
that our knowledge of others is by inference. For him, I know that other people
exist as I am, when I see them doing similar things that I do. So this
similarity of actions make me to infer or conclude that the other persons exist
as I do. On the contrary, Jean-Paul Sartre and Heidegger reject this view of
Berkeley by positing that our knowledge of others is part of our
self-knowledge. For them, man discovers himself and becomes aware of himself in
the midst of others. This existentialists position seems to be more tenable
than that of Berkeley because man is by nature a social being who is
essentially linked with others. Hence, he cannot be conscious of his being in isolation, without at the same time
being conscious of others. This makes Descartes’ cogito ego sum untenable.
3.
What
are the idols of Francis Bacon?
4.
Differentiate
between rationalism and empiricism and give two knowledge theories of each of
their proponents.
What is
rationalism? Rationalism is the philosophical view that emphasizes the ability
of human reason to grasp fundamental truths about the world without the aid of
sense impressions.[1]
It is an epistemic theory, which boldly emphasises that the mind is the only
source of true knowledge. Conversely, empiricism is a theory that claims that
knowledge is obtained solely from sense experience.[2]It is the theory that
experience is the source of all knowledge, hence, it denies that human beings
possess inborn knowledge or that they can derive knowledge through the exercise
of reason alone.[3]
By and large, it is very pertinent to note that the disagreement between rationalists
and empiricists is primarily based on the sources of our concepts and
knowledge. Each of them primarily tries to respond to the question: How can we
know? Whereas the rationalists claim that knowledge is gained through reason,
the empiricists claim that it is by means of experience or sense perception.
Among the exponents of rationalism are
Descartes, Spinoza and Leibniz. Let us consider the theory of Descartes. Rene
Descartes (1596-1650) was a scientist, mathematician and a philosopher who is
popularly known as the father of Modern philosophy. Being unsatisfied and
worried about the uncertainty and confusion rooted in philosophy owing to
doubtful and shaky foundation, Descartes resorted to the mathematical method as
the only reliable path to attaining clear, certain and distinct indubitable
truth. In addition to this, he employed the method of systematic or methodic
doubt. Consequently, he realised and developed 3Ds namely, Distance, Dream and
Devil, which he employed in doubting everything he ever knew in order to
reconstruct philosophy on a firm and solid foundation on which the
epistemological and philosophical edifice would be erected. Thus, he despised
Aristotelian logic and adopted the principles of intuition and deduction as the
only rational and reliable procedure to the attainment of knowledge, hence, he
rejected sense experience. After series of doubt, he confirmed his existence as
a thinking being (res Cogitans). This is because, for him, if I doubt, I think
and if I think therefore I exist- cogito ergo sum. Hence, the cogito became the
underlying absolute principle and the only fundamental and indubitable truth
upon which Descartes rested his epistemology and the development of other
principles such as innate principle and the existence of God.
John Locke is the
founding father of modern British empiricism. In his epistemology, he begins by
rejecting Descartes’ doctrine of innate ideas and affirms sense experience as
the source of knowledge. For him, before sense experience, our mind is like “a
white paper”[4]
(tabular rasa) on which nothing is written. He divided experience into two:
sensation and reflection. Sensation refers to the experience of our external
sensations which provides us with primary and secondary qualities,[5] whereas, reflection is the
notice the mind takes of its own operators which enables us to get new ideas.
He posits two kinds of ideas namely simple and complex. The former are
impressions directly caused by things outside our minds, hence, simple ideas
are nothing but copies or representations of things.
Strengths and
Weaknesses cum Point of Convergence
It is pertinent to note
that both rationalism and empiricism contribute tremendously in the development
of Epistemology. However, each of them
has its weaknesses. For instance, in refuting the rationalism of Descartes,
Kant posits that the ability to be aware of one’s existence presupposes the
real existence of the external world. Again, Kant argues that the method of the
rationalists leads to insoluble contradictions (or as he called them
antinomies) – such as the universe is limited and limitless. Those antinomies
are intractable because the rationalist epistemology takes for granted a kind
of pure knowledge of external objects independent of any sensational
experience.[6]On the other hand, empiricism has
been critiqued in a number of ways.
Phenomenologically, Hume's notion of
"impression" does not account for the way that we actually do
experience colours and qualities. When I see a red house, for instance, I do
not just have an impression of red by itself, but the redness “of” something. A
"secondary quality" such as colour cannot be abstracted from the
thing to which it belongs. In this way, empiricism is no more faithful to
experience than rationalism. Similarly, empiricism does not acknowledge
that experience is contextual. When I see a thing, I do not see it in isolation
from the world. It is always given in a context: the chair is on the floor,
next to a table, in a room, etc. There is always a "background" against
which a thing appears.[7]
Furthermore, Descartes and Locke have remarkably
similar views on the nature of our ideas, even though Descartes takes many to
be innate, while Locke ties them all to experience. Nonetheless, there
is a concern here which we have to raise. Where does the activity of the
creation of both impressions and ideas take place? What is it that reflects on
the impressions to give rise to the faint images of ideas? Usually, such
activities would be explained in terms of the faculties of a mind but Hume does
not allow for such an entity. According to Hume, the mind belongs alongside the
ideas it purportedly creates, in the realm of fiction. A mirage, for instance,
on a tarred road in a hot afternoon which the senses perceive from a distance
as a large pool of water disappears on getting closer. Therefore, sense
perception alone without reason as Kant would affirm in his Critique of
Practical Reason (1788) cannot be relied on. To affirm that sense perception is
all that is means to affirm that, nothing else can be except that which is
accessible to the senses. Plato, and
later supported by Descartes, faulted the evidence of sense experience alone on
the grounds that though it is relevant, it is not exclusive criterion for
looking at reality.
Conclusion
Rationalism and empiricism are two main epistemic doctrines,
which are opposing to each other. The former involves the following theses:
intuition, deduction and innate
knowledge which provide us with knowledge a
priori, that is, knowledge gained independently of sense experience. In
contrast, the latter offers us knowledge a posteriori, which is knowledge that
is dependent on sense experience. Thus, whereas rationalism claims the
indispensability and superiority of reason as a source of knowledge, empiricism
claims the indispensability and superiority of sense experience as the source
of knowledge. However, neither of them can fully account for the phenomenon and
universal knowledge. Because, while rationalism provides the form without
content, empiricism provides content without form. Hence, only in their
synthesis is knowledge possible.[8] For
knowledge is partly a priori and partly a posteriori. Thus, the two theories-
rationalism and empiricism are needed for proper understanding and acquisition
of knowledge.
i.
Rene
Descartes
ii.
John
Locke
iii.
David
Hume
iv.
George
Berkeley
5.
What
are the theories of Truth?
There are three
traditional theories of truth, namely, the correspondence theory, the coherence
theory and the pragmatic theory.
i.
Correspondence
theory of truth: it makes two claims; first, a proposition is true if and only
if it corresponds to the facts. Second, a proposition is false if and only if
it fails to correspond to the facts. This implies that the truth of a
proposition or belief is dependent on the facts or upon the way, the world is.
Hence, the truthfulness of our proposition does not depend just on what we
believe about that thing, but on what is really is in reality. For this theory
truth is not relative.
ii.
The
Coherence Theory: it comprises the consistence between what is said and all
other enunciation or judgements which are previously known and accepted to be true. In other words, it
presupposes the principle of non contradiction. For an assertion to be true, it
has to be in harmony with already known facts. It holds that a statement is
true if there is a coherence between the statement and a systematic body of
statements already know to be true. If a proposition coheres with prior
propositions that are known to be true, then the proposition is true. On the
other hand, if a proposition is in conflict with other propositions already
known to be true, then the statement in question is false.
iii.
The
Pragmatic theory: it holds that a statement or theory is true if it works in
practice. An idea is true if it works and leads to beneficial results. This
theory was propounded by C. S. Peirce and William James.
iv.
The
dialectical theory: it holds that truth is a process of becoming, since reality
itself is in the state of becoming.
6.
What
is scepticism?
Scepticism is
doubt or the denial of the possibility of knowledge. Knowledge implies
certainty. To claim to know something implies being sure or being certain about
that thing. However, some philosophers have doubted the possibility of
certainty. In fact epistemology developed through the ages in a bid to respond
to the challenges of the sceptics. It has grown in its bid to address the
following questions posed by the sceptics: Does knowledge exist? If yes, in
what form does it exist, what is its nature? Is it subjective or objective? How
do we know that we know (that is the justification of our knowledge claim)?
What is the source of our knowledge? Is knowledge inherent in us or given? Can
we actually obtain a certainty of knowledge? How
can we gain knowledge? To what extent can we know? In what sense or
degree can we say that we know in this changing world as posited by Heraclitus?
Scepticism is of different kinds namely, universal scepticism which is the
doubt of every possible knowledge. it claims that nobody can be sure of
anything since certainty or knowledge is beyond human mind. The sophists were
the first group of sceptics in Western philosophy. They were sceptical and
critical about traditional beliefs and knowledge claims. One of them by name
Gorgias argues that nothing exists, that even if anything were to exist, it
could not be known, even if such a thing could be known, it could not be
communicated to others. Therefore, knowledge is impossible. Again Protagoras
posits that man is the measure of all things, of things that are that they are
and things that are not that they are not. Hence, for him knowledge is
subjective and relative that is the way an individual sees it. Pyrrho of Elis
with his disciple Timon of Philus, another sophists, denied the possibility of
certain knowledge since for him the human mind cannot penetrate into the inner
nature of things. hence, we can only know the phenomena and not the noumena. Furthermore,
Carneades of Cyrene, founder of the New Academy, was sceptical about the possibility of
proving anything through syllogistic argument since the premises of any
syllogism are based on assumption which would require to be proved first before
being used to prove anything else. But to prove them would require prior
premises also based on assumption which required to be proved before being
used, this process would continue to infinity.
David Humes’ scepticism is derived from
his determination to push empiricism to its logical conclusion. Hume’s
philosophy shows clearly that the logical conclusion of empiricism is
scepticism. The root of Hume’s scepticism is his criticism of the principle of
causality. He denied the necessary connection, universality and uniformity of
nature since they are not empirically provable. For him, that one thing causes
another is not part of our empirical experience because we do not see
empirically the necessary connection between the two. Necessity and
universality are not part of our empirical experience, hence, any knowledge
based on them is unreliable and invalid. That the future will resemble the past
is nothing but assumption and is unprovable. Thus he denies the necessary
connection between cause and effect since the connection is synthetic than
being necessary. Thus, Hume’s denial of principle of causality leads to
complete scepticism.
Critique:
like st Augustine, anybody who claims to know that all knowledge is doubtful is
contradicting himself. This is because
the very fact that scepticism is true as claimed by the sceptics is a clear
proof that there is possibility of certain knowledge. so it is
self-contradictory for a sceptic to say that he knows that nobody can know
anything or that he is sure that nobody can be sure of anything. Augustine went
further to argue that universal scepticism is impossible because the person who
says that nothing can be known for certain knows for certain at least that he
exists. To the objection that a person could be deceived into thinking that he
exists whereas he does not really exist.
Augustine replies that to be deceived is a proof of one’s existence.
Thus, if I am deceived, then I exist -si fallor sum. Conversely, scepticism
gave rise to the development of epistemology and in that sense it has helped
epistemology to grow. Thus, scepticism has been, and will always remain an
indispensable part of epistemology. The big challenge to scepticism is how to
account the fact that no knowledge is built on a vacuum. For every knowledge
has a starting point by which we reason. For there must be something that we
must take for granted for one… again we have reasons to believe that our
premises are true.
However,
scepticism is very relevant because it makes philosophy self-critical and keeps
it honest and ree of dogamatism.
[1] Samuel Enoch Stumpf, Philosophy: History and Problems (New
York: McGraw-Hill, Inc.1994), p. 938.
[2]William F. Lawhead, The Voyage of Discovery: A Historical
Introduction to Philosophy (Belmont: Wadsworth, 2004) P. 574.
[3] Samuel Enoch Stumpf, Philosophy: History and Problems (New
York: McGraw-Hill, Inc.1994), P.936.
[4] J. Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, edited by J. A. St. John
(London, 1898), p. 205.
[5] Ibid., pp. 243-244.
[8] Cf. R. Scruton, Kant (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1982), p. 18.
Comments
Post a Comment