NOTION OF HAPPINESS AND FRIENDSHIP IN ARISTOTLE’S NICOMACHEAN ETHICS


NOTION OF HAPPINESS AND FRIENDSHIP IN ARISTOTLE’S NICOMACHEAN ETHICS






INTRODUCTION
            One would assume that one of the general purposes of the course Reproductive Health, STIs and HIV is to provide man with the required knowledge and skills of how to live and remain healthy. According to the World Health Organization, being healthy implies being in a complete state of complete physical, mental and social well-being and not just the absence of disease and infirmity.[1] Having this in mind, it is rational to wonder what Aristotle’s notions of Friendship and Happiness have in common with reproductive health. Considering the definition of health given above, it is plausible to affirm that Aristotle’s notions of Friendship and Happiness is connected to this course. This is because being in a friendship that promotes happiness can indeed enhance one’s physical, mental and social well-being.
            Again, we can assume that among the aims of this course is to enhance man’s goodness in himself and in the society. According to Meliksah Demir, the notions of Friendship and Happiness are strongly intermixed in Aristotle’s idea of goodness, and in this, goodness and friendship are inseparably interrelated. The understanding of two aspects of Aristotle’s idea of goodness is important to grasp this harmony between goodness and friendship. The idea of goodness being a particular thing or an entity and seeing the goodness in a material sense or manner were refuted. So, he conceives goodness as a transcendent phenomenon that should be grasped as an action-based process with the purpose of an outcome which is eudaimonia, that is, a Greek word for Happiness. The term eudaimonia has been translated also to mean human-flourishing. Hence, as McIntyre said of Aristotle, goodness is associated with any action whose aim is to promote happiness.[2]
            In considering Aristotle’s notions of Friendship and Happiness this paper shall consider first the concept of friendship and if there are types of friendship, then it shall be considered before looking at the reciprocity of friendship. After which, we shall examine what happiness is and its place in friendship. That will be followed by the goal of human life and then the conclusion.
In the discourse of friendship and its importance in the human life, Aristotle posits that “no one would choose to live without friends, even if he had every other good thing.”[3] Following his line of thought, friendship seems to be present by nature in parents towards their offspring and vice-versa. Also, the tie between city-states seems to be held by friendship. But the question of what friends consists in eludes many. So, some claim that friendship is a kind of likeness and that those who are alike are friends.[4] In still clarifying the concept of friendship, he asserts that we cannot talk about friendly affection between animate and inanimate objects. This is because there is no form of reciprocity of friendly affection and no wishing for their good. If not, he holds that it would be ridiculous to wish good things for a wine.[5]
In his view, friendship is a bridge between the moral virtues and the highest life of philosophy.[6] So, friendship is an essential safeguard for the life, property, and political freedom or power that virtue requires as equipment for its full exercise; and it provides the guidance that young men need, the assistance that the weak and the elderly need, and the clarity of insight that even the best kind human being need in order to act and to think.[7] In all of this, friendship appears less as an end in itself than as a crucial condition for the individuals and virtuous activity. More so, Aristotle notes that friendship is necessary in such a manner that it is rooted in our animalistic nature. Nature has implanted in many animals, and especially in human beings, a love for those who are kindred of children and parents above all, also of fellow tribesmen and even of the whole human race.[8]
According to Aristotle, there are three kinds of friendship: the friendship of utility, the friendship of pleasure and friendship of goodness. overall, friendship consists of equal exchanges, whether of utility, pleasantness or goodness. However, there are some relationships that by their nature exist between two people that are unequal, for instance, the relationship between father and son, ruler and subject and so on. We shall now discuss the kinds of friendship in details.

According to Aristotle, the friendship of utility is kind of friendship where both people derive some benefits from each other. They do not love each other in themselves, but in so far as some benefits accrue to them from each other. This kind of friendship is only incidental since the object of the affection is not loved for the kind of person he is, but for providing some good.[9] In other words, the friend is not loved for his own sake, but for 999the sake of some benefit received by the other. Aristotle notes that these friendships are not permanent, it ceases as soon as one partner is no longer pleasant or useful to the other.[10] For him, when the motive of the friendship has passed away, the friendship itself is dissolved, having existed merely as a means to an end.
In Aristotle’s thought, the friendship of utility seems to occur most frequently among the elderly because, at an advanced age, most people do not pursue pleasure but profit. This kind of friendship can also occur among those that have reached the prime of their life and young people whose object in life is to make progress, sometimes regardless of the means. Friends of this kind have no further need of been in a relationship if they are not mutually beneficial. They find each other pleasant only to the extent that they have hopes of some good coming out of it.[11] The traditional friendship between the host and guest is also placed in this group of friendship.

The friendship of pleasure is the kind of friendship that is mostly seen among young people. Their lives are guided by their emotion, and they pursue most intensely what they find pleasant and what the moment brings. As they advance in years, different things come to be pleasant for them.[12] In this kind of friendship, people love their friends not for friendship sake, but for the sake of the pleasure they receive. This kind of friendship is easier to form but can easily dissolve. According to Aristotle, young people are prone to fall in love, since the greater part of falling in love is a matter of emotion and basically based on pleasure. They form a friendship and give it up again so quickly that the change often takes place almost the same day.[13]

The third kind of friendship according to Aristotle is the friendship of goodness. In this kind of friendship, both people admire the other’s goodness. It is the perfect form of friendship because it is friendship between the good people who are alike in virtue. The people involved in this kind of friendship desires the good and respect of each other. They are good in themselves and wish the good of their friends for their friends’ sake, who are friends in the fullest sense since they love each other for themselves and not accidentally.[14]
            In this way, their friendship endures so long as they continue to be good, and each is good relatively to his friend as well as absolutely, since they are both good absolutely and profitable to each other.[15] Each is pleasant in both ways since good men are pleasant both absolutely and to each other since everyone is pleased by his own actions; and therefore by actions that resemble his own, and the actions of all good men are the same or similar.
            The idea of reciprocity projects an undertone of a relationship that is closely bonded by a mutualistic cooperation, existing between two persons or among a group of people. It is understood as some form of accessible ground, where one’s level of association is based on a perceived sense of interactive freedom, particularly between friends. So, one can rightly hold on to the affirmation that determines the reciprocity of friendship -as that inner drive that unites people together, with the aim of satisfying one’s individualistic interest.[16]
Admittedly, the fundamental aspect of unanimity that is concerned with friendship, introduces the mind to the notion of what friendly relation entails. This expresses an ideal reality that is occasioned by the coming together of persons, with the aim of getting what they want or desire. It is incited by an egoistic motive to get oneself involved in a relationship, in order to actualize an attainment of a gainful reward from such friendly relation.[17] Nevertheless, there resides a contrastive line that differentiates a kind of friendly relation that is not solely based on the egoistic kind of union between persons. This can be seen from the union that exists among good men. It is a kind that is free from a friendly relation that promotes the pursuit of one’s selfish interest.[18]
Interestingly, the activity of love is made more evident in the proceedings of this friendly relation. The human makeup is oriented toward having a deeper love for things acquired through personal efforts and hard work. This accounts for the reason why there are persons who love things or themselves more than any other thing or person. But by the virtue of what is worthy of our moral expectations and responsibilities, it is demanded of every individual to engage in a certain friendly relation that is void of any self-interest or personal gain. These are the set of people that are considered good -those who take actions in honour of their friend’s sake by sacrificing one’s own interest.[19]
            The concept of happiness is difficult to pin down. Hence, many scholars have posited different things attempting to give a clear notion of what happiness is. When giving an authentic description of what happiness is, one would expect that it will need to fit into the reality of different variables such as that different personalities, situations, opinions and so on, that have the capacity of changing enthusiastically from one person to another. Amid the unsettled notions of what happiness entails, some are of the view that happiness has to do with having fun. This can be in the form of playing games, having sex, or other activities. Some, however, opine that if they become rich, then they will be happy. Furthermore, some believe that happiness is about having power over others.[20]
            Considering the different notions of happiness, Aristotle seems to offer a more rational and universal approach to happiness that every rational being can reckon with easily.  He began by presenting the notion that happiness can be achieved through virtuous living, which one can plausibly assert that it is also one of the aims acquiring knowledge about man’s reproductive health, STDs and HIV. In Aristotle’s view, virtue is a praiseworthy state of character or mind and soul.[21] Hence, he posits that “the happy man will be happy throughout his life; for always, or by preference to everything else, if he will be engaged in virtuous actions.”[22]
            The word eudaimonia according to Aristotle is a Greek word which denotes happiness. So, certain things are chosen for the sake of something else while some are chosen for their own sake. Those things which are chosen for their own sake, are said to be the final end. This description seems to apply to happiness above all else, for we always chose happiness as an end in itself and never for the sake of something else.[23] In describing what happiness is, he posits that “we call final without qualification that which is always desirable in itself and never for the sake of something else.”[24] This implies that if one is happy, there is nothing that can make the person happier. This is because happiness is considered as good in itself.[25] According to Aristotle, the happiness which is the highest of all ends rests on different particular ends and each is an end in itself. Thus, people attain happiness by reaching a multiplicity of ends. This variety of ends could be family, friends, education and financial well-being. These ends reveal part of who we are and what we do. Thus, while the highest good that can and should be achieved is happiness, this ultimate good is built on a series of lesser goods.[26] 
In the Aristotelian sense, friendship is understood as a situation whereby one person loves and wishes another person good and the other person reciprocates the love and good wish.[27] In that line, he posits that there are three kinds of friendship which are simultaneously linked and equal in number to the principal bases of a person loving and wishing good to another person.[28]
Furthermore, Aristotle upholds that only the third kind for friendly relationship is the perfect one among the three. This is so because he believes that it is only in this kind that a person loves and wishes the other person well not for the sake of any mutual advantage or pleasure but for the sake of the persons itself.[29] More so, he maintains that this is the perfect model of friendship and it contains the other two kinds since each party benefit the other and also find considerable pleasure in the relationship as well.[30]  
Moreover, since happiness is the ultimate end in which every human action and inquiry tend towards, one may then ask how friendship relate to the attainment of happiness. Aristotle had already posited the need for virtues in order to attain happiness, and also concedes that a person must possess other goods such as friends and wealth as well.[31] He upholds that a deficiency in these other goods might endanger a person’s happiness. Nevertheless, since he considers happiness as that which is sought for its sake alone and not for another thing, it is explicit that it is only the third kind of friendship that happiness can be placed within. 
The question of the goal of the human life is one that has endured from time immemorial. In the unfolding of history, many theories have been offered to answer this question. These theories have their discrepancies, but something remains unchangeable in them; it is the fact that the goal of human life is a certain state of life that requires some kind of action. What is this goal then? Pierre de Chardin tries to explain it thus:
In the world of mechanized matter, all bodies obey the laws of a universal gravitation; similarly, in the world of vitalized matter, all organized beings, even the very lowest, steer themselves and progress towards that quarter in which the greatest measure of well-being is to be found.[32]

Pierre de Chardin states that it is well-being that all humans naturally seek. In truth, this is the equivalent of the concept of eudaimonia that philosophers theorized on. However, for the purpose of this work, we shall focus on the philosophy of Aristotle. This philosophy is rooted in his metaphysics of teleology or the end or purpose or function of things which is the way to discover their real nature.
“Aristotle begins his book on ethics by observing that all human action aims at some end.”[33] He also observed that some ends are merely instrumental, they are not ends per se, we pursue them so that we can achieve other goals. The instrumental or intermediate goals continue to lead from one goal to another, however, it cannot continue ad infinitum, otherwise, the whole process would make no sense. These intermediate goals must ultimately be focused on a final good which is desired for the sake of itself and not for another.
            According to Aristotle, happiness is that final end which every human being pursues for its own sake. He noticed that when people act in a certain way, we can ask why they are acting or acted that way, or why people want this or that. However, it is quite absurd to ask the question “why do you want to be happy?”  That all humans desire happiness does not need any justification. However, Aristotle remarks that people hold different opinions on what happiness is. The subject is associated with things such as pleasure, wealth and honour among other things.
            In De Metaphisca of Aristotle, the real nature of anything is discoverable in its purpose or function. “Moreover, this will constitute its virtue or the standard of its excellence.”[34] Therefore a good carpenter is known for fulfilling the goal of carpentry, which is construction. The good eye performs the function of seeing. In a like manner, a human being ought to fulfill its end in other to find fulfillment or be known as a good human being. The way to achieve this “must be unique and special to human beings that we do not share in common with other creatures. For this reason, Aristotle cautions that we will go astray if we equate happiness with pleasure.”[35] Those who hold such opinion do not know a life appropriate to human beings but rather to beasts.
            Saying that the goal of human life should be something uniquely human, it is already obvious that Aristotle meant a rational principle. Evidently, in his Nicomachean Ethics, he opined that the function of a man is generically an activity of the soul in accordance with reason. Accordingly, the function of a good man is to live in accordance with virtue, “and if the virtues are many, then according to the best and most complete virtue.”[36] Thus, he further averred that the goal of human life is afforded by nature, and which is the essence of our humanity.
            A further description of the purpose of human life shows that it entails living in a particular way -which is thinking and acting. The reason for this is that though we are rational beings, we also feel, desire and act. Therefore, the path to happiness involves a rational scrutiny of the right principles to follow, and then discipline our feelings and appetites according to those principles. For this purpose, two kinds of human excellence are required. They are intellectual virtue and moral virtue, also known as the excellence of intelligence and excellence of character. If either or both are neglected, then there cannot be a good life.

            Though Aristotle agrees that the goal of human life is happiness, he also opines that there are other things that human beings need to be happy and one of such things is good health. Since Aristotle submits that to be happy, both the intellectual and moral virtues need to be active in our actions, we shall show how this relates to happiness by showing two ways in which the will operates. The first manifests strength which is known as enkrasia, the other shows weakness and is known as akrasia.
            Enkrasia is the ability of the will to recognize a certain good and pursue it, or a certain evil, and avoid it. Akrasia is the opposite. Here, the will either choose a recognized evil or avoids a known good. The pursuit of happiness necessarily demands that we take the part of enkrasia if we are to protect the health aspect of our happiness. This means that having been enlightened by the course Reproductive health, STIs and HIV we now understand the things we should do to maintain our health, and we ought to do those things.
            Manifesting traits of the enkratic for instance will mean that, since we have been taught that smoking puts some vital organs at risk of damage, the intellectual aspect of happiness has been fulfilled. It now behooves us to develop the moral will to avoid smoking in other to preserve our health. Knowing that smoking or any other risk factor is dangerous to our health, and yet not avoiding them is a show of an akratic disposition. At the end, when our health fails, it has a negative effect on our pursuit of happiness. It is in this way that the goal of human life relates to the aims and objective of this course.
            The primary task of this paper is to explore Aristotle's notion of friend and happiness. To carry out this task, we began by examining the concept of friendship and the three types of friendship that are found in the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle. In doing this, we came to the realization that true friendship according to him is not and should not be parasitic, rather there should be a mutual harmony among friends. Coming to this knowledge of true friendship, led us to consider the concept of reciprocity of friendship. Bearing in mind the task of this paper which has to do with friendship and happiness, we then explored the concept of happiness and its place in friendship. In discussing the place of happiness in friendship, we reached the knowledge that since it is only in the third kind of friendship that is sought for its own sake without any ulterior motive, and happiness is sought for its sake alone. Hence, it is only in this kind of friendship that we find happiness.
            But why should one bother to consider friendship and happiness? What has this got to do with the course: Reproductive Health, STIs, and HIV? Why should we bother to inquire the kind of friendship that harbours true happiness? These questions led us to consider the goal of human life. we then got to a plausible truth that the two kinds of friendship that are sought for the sake of something else, dispose us to factors that hinder our mental, physical and social well-being. Thus, only the third kind of friendship which consists of being truly happy enhances our health.



Ann Ward, Contemplating Friendship in Aristotle Ethics New York: Suny Press, 2016.

Aristotle, “Nichomachean Ethics,” in Basic Work of Aristotle, ed. Richard Mckeon New York:    Modern Library, 2001.

Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, (trans. Hippocrates G. Apostle). Iowa: The Peripatetic Press, 1984.

Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, in Marin Ostwald (Ed) Swartmore College, 1962, p. 218.

Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics: Books VIII and IX Trans. by Michael Pakaluk New York: Oxford             University Press, 1998.

Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle trans. by Robert Williams London: Longmans,     Green and Co., 1869, 1100, b. 18

F. H. Peters, M. A.  The Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle, Tenth Edition London: Kegan Paul,      Trench, Trubner & Co., Ltd., 1906.

Gary Madvin and Geraldine Markel, Finding Happiness with Aristotle as Your Guide       Bloomington: iUniverse, Inc., 2009.

Gerard J. Hughes, Aristotle on Ethics, Tim Crane and Jonathan Wolff (eds.) New York: Taylor    & Francis e-Library, 2003.

Lorraine Smith Pangle, Aristotle and the Philosophy of Friendship.

Luigino Bruni, Reciprocity, Altruism and the Civil Society: In Praise of Heterogeneity New         York: Routledge, 2008.

Martin Ostwald, Aristotle Nichomachean Ethics, The Library of Liberal Arts, Oskar Piest             Founder, Swarthmore College, 1962.

Meliksah Demir, Friendship and Happiness: Across the Life-Span and Cultures New York:         Springer Dordrecht Heidelberg, 2015.

P. I Ahmed and George V. Coelho, Toward a New Definition of Health: Pyschosocial      Dimensions New York: Plenum Press, 1979.

Pierre Teilhard de Chardin, On Happiness. Trans. by Rene Hague New York: Harper and Row    Publishers, 1973.    


Richard Kreaut, “Aristotle Ethics”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2018         Edition, Edward N. Zalta (ed.), forthcoming URL = https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/aristotle-ethics/.

Richard Kreaut, “Aristotle Ethics”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

William F. Lawhead, The Voyage of Discovery: A Historical Introduction to Philosophy Belmont:             Wadsworth Group, 2002.  



[1] Cf. P. I Ahmed and George V. Coelho, Toward a New Definition of Health: Pyschosocial Dimensions (New York: Plenum Press, 1979), P. 113
[2] Cf. Meliksah Demir, Friendship and Happiness: Across the Life-Span and Cultures (New York: Springer Dordrecht Heidelberg, 2015), P. 61
[3] Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics: Books VIII and IX Trans. by Michael Pakaluk (New York: Oxford University Press, 1998), P. 1
[4] Cf. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics: Books VIII and IX Trans. by Michael Pakaluk (New York: Oxford University Press, 1998), PP. 1-2
[5] Cf. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics: Books VIII and IX Trans. by Michael Pakaluk (New York: Oxford University Press, 1998), P. 3
[6] Cf. Ann Ward, Contemplating Friendship in Aristotle Ethics (New York: Suny Press, 2016), p. 100.
[7] Ann Ward, Contemplating Friendship in Aristotle Ethics, p. 101.
[8] Cf. Lorraine Smith Pangle, Aristotle and the Philosophy of Friendship, p. 16.
[9] Cf. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, in Marin Ostwald (Ed) Swartmore College, 1962, p. 218.
[10] Cf. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, pp. 218-219
[11] Cf. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, p. 219.
[12] Cf. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, p. 219.
[13] Cf. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, p. 219.
[14] Cf. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, p. 219.
[15] Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, p. 219.
[16] Cf. Luigino Bruni, Reciprocity, Altruism and the Civil Society: In Praise of Heterogeneity (New York: Routledge, 2008), 32-33.
[17] Cf. Aristotle, “Nichomachean Ethics,” in Basic Work of Aristotle, ed. Richard Mckeon (New York: Modern Library, 2001), 1084.
[18] Cf. Aristotle, “Nichomachean Ethics,” 1084.
[19] Cf. Aristotle, “Nichomachean Ethics,” 1086.
[20] Cf. Gary Madvin and Geraldine Markel, Finding Happiness with Aristotle as Your Guide (Bloomington: iUniverse, Inc., 2009), P. 16
[21] Cf. Gary Madvin and Geraldine Markel, Finding Happiness with Aristotle as Your Guide (Bloomington: iUniverse, Inc., 2009), P. 17
[22] Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle trans. by Robert Williams (London: Longmans, Green and Co., 1869), 1100, b. 18
[23] Cf. Martin Ostwald, Aristotle Nichomachean Ethics, The Library of Liberal Arts, Oskar Piest Founder, (Swarthmore College, 1962), p. 15.
[24] Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle trans. by Robert Williams (London: Longmans, Green and Co., 1869), 1o97, a. 30
[25] Cf. Gary Madvin and Geraldine Markel, Finding Happiness with Aristotle as Your Guide (Bloomington: iUniverse, Inc., 2009), P.18
[26] Cf. Gary Madvin and Geraldine Markel, Finding Happiness with Aristotle as Your Guide (Bloomington: iUniverse, Inc., 2009), P. 20
[27] Cf. F. H. Peters, M. A. (Trans.) The Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle, Tenth Edition (London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co., Ltd., 1906) p. 254
[28] Cf. Gerard J. Hughes, Aristotle on Ethics, Tim Crane and Jonathan Wolff (eds.) (New York: Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2003) pp. 169-170
[29] Cf. Richard Kreaut, “Aristotle Ethics”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), forthcoming URL = https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/aristotle-ethics/.
[30] Cf. Richard Kreaut, “Aristotle Ethics”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
[31] Cf. Gerard J. Hughes, Aristotle on Ethics, Tim Crane and Jonathan Wolff (eds.) (New York: Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2003) pp. 26-27
[32] Pierre Teilhard de Chardin, On Happiness. (Trans. Rene Hague). New York: Harper and Row Publishers, 1973. Pg. 7.       
[33] William F. Lawhead, The Voyage of Discovery: A Historical Introduction to Philosophy. Belmont: Wadsworth Group, 2002. Pg. 80.
[34]William F. Lawhead, The Voyage of Discovery: A Historical Introduction to Philosophy. Pg. 81.
[35] William F. Lawhead, The Voyage of Discovery: A Historical Introduction to Philosophy. Pg. 81.
[36] Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, (trans. Hippocrates G. Apostle). Iowa: The Peripatetic Press, 1984. (NE 1.6).

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

SUMMARY OF PROVIDENTISSIMUS DEUS, ENCYCLICAL LETTER OF POPE LEO XIII ON THE STUDY OF THE HOLY SCRIPTURE.

summary and appraisal of chapters one, two and three of the book The African Origin of Greek Philosophy: An Exercise in Afrocentrism, by Innocent C. Onyewuenyi.

THE LAST THREE WAYS TO PROVES GOD'S EXISTENCE BY THOMAS AQUINAS