PERSON AND COMMUNITY
PERSON
AND COMMUNITY
The
characteristic of communitarianism (or communal living) is one aspect that
distinguishes Africans from westerners. This distinguishing characteristic of
Africans has attracted a host of contributions. Central here are Ifeanyi
Menkiti and Kwame Gyekye. These men champion radical communitarianism and
moderate communitarianism respectively. Let us move to present their views.
IFEANYI
MENKITI (RADICAL COMMUNITARIAN)
Menkiti begins by contrasting the divergences between
the western and African views of person vis-à-vis the community.
Firstly,
according to Menkiti, albeit most western views of man abstract this or that
feature (rationality, memory, or will) of a lone individual and then proceed to
make it the defining or essential characteristic which entities aspiring to the
description man must have, the African view of man denies this but defines man
by reference to the environing community and the social circumstances that
shape the individual. This, J.S Mbiti says is summed up in the statement “I am
because we are, and since we are, therefore I am.” Affirming this, Menkiti
opines that from this dictum, it is to be appositely concluded that the reality
of the communal world takes precedence over the reality of individual life
histories, whatever these may be. This primacy is meant to apply both
ontologically, and with regard to epistemic accessibility. Hence, it is in
rootedness in an on-going human community that the individual comes to see
himself/herself as a man/woman, and it is by first knowing this community as a
stubborn perduring fact of the psychophysical world that the individual also
comes to know himself/herself as a durable, more or less permanent, fact of this
world.
The
second point of contrast is the processual nature of being in African thought.
According to Menkiti, persons become persons only after a process of
incorporation. Without incorporation into this or that community, individuals
are considered mere danglers to whom the description ‘person’ does not apply.
Personhood, contra western thought,
is achieved and not simply given by mere birth as it is in western thought.
Thus, in the light of the above, says Menkiti, the western view goes for
minimal definition of the person, the African view goes for maximal definition
of the person.
Moving
further to consolidate and develop his views on personhood, Menkiti avers that
personhood is attained not merely ontologically given, it is something at which
individuals could fail, at which they could be incompetent or ineffective,
better or worse. He substantiates this by given two arguments.
The
first is what I call the ‘It’ argument. Here, Menkiti argues that, in many
African languages (English included), children and new-borns are referred to as
‘it’. Although, we could refer to such as he or she, but, we have a choice of
using ‘it’ whereas no such choice abounds in referring to older persons. In
this light too, a significant symmetry exists between the opening phase of an
individual’s quest for personhood and the terminal phase of that quest. Both
are marked by an absence of incorporation and this absence is made abundantly
evident by the related absence of collectively conferred names. This is clear
because in African societies, the ultimate termination of personal existence is
also marked by an ‘it’ designation, thus, the same depersonalized reference
marking the beginning of personal existence, also marks the end of that
existence. After birth, the individual goes through the different rites of
incorporation, including those of initiation at puberty time, before becoming a
full person in the eyes of the community. And then, of course, there is
procreation, old age, death and entering into the community of departed
ancestral spirits- a community viewed as continuous with the community of
living men and women, and with which it is conceived as being in constant interaction.
The inhabitants of this ancestral community, Menkiti (following Mbiti) calls
‘living dead’. This name is invoked because the ancestral dead are neither dead
in the world of the spirits, nor in the memory of living men/women who continue
to remember them, and implore their help via libation and sacrificial offering.
But, at the stage of ancestral existence, the personhood of the dead remain which
make them to be addressed by their various names. But later, after several
generations, the ancestors cease to be remembered by their personal names
(nameless dead) and slide into personal non-existence, becoming mere ‘its’,
ending their earthly sojourn as they had started out, and falling back into
unincorporated non-persons.
The
second is what I call the ‘grief’ argument. Here, Menkiti argues that in
African societies, there is a relative absence of ritualized grief when the
death of a young child occurs, whereas with the death of an older person, the
burial ceremony becomes more elaborate and the grief more ritualized, thus,
indicating a significant difference in the conferral of ontological status, and
affirming that personhood is attained not immediately given by mere birth.
If
personhood then is attained, does mere incorporation suffice? Menkiti would answer
this question by saying that personhood is to be attained via participation in
communal life. Through the discharge of the various obligations defined by
one’s stations. The carrying out of these obligations transforms one from the
‘it’ status of early childhood (marked by an absence of moral functions), into
the person-status of later years (marked by a widened maturity of ethical
sense). This moral maturity, and the fulfillment of moral mores and ethical
norms are necessary for personhood attainment, and this is surely absent in
children and infants in Menkiti’s theses.
On
the whole, for Menkiti, in African societies, unlike western, there is the
ontological priority, primacy and independence of the community. The community
gives rise to persons, and personhood is acquired not merely given by birth.
This acquisition is by incorporation and ethical sense fulfillment.
KWAME
GYEKYE (MODERATE COMMUNITARIAN)
According
to Kwame Gyekye, social structure is a necessary feature of every human
society, but it evolves (unlike Menkiti) to give effect to certain conceptions
of human nature, and provide a framework for both the realization of the
potentials, goals and hopes of the individual members of the society, and the
continuous existence and survival of the society. Citing Senghor, Dickson and
Kenyatta, Gyekye avers that communal life and communitarian ethos of the
African culture (which rules out isolationism, individualism and eccentricity)
is central in African societies, evident in African socio-ethical thought and
indisputably reflected in African societies.
But
what, asks Gyekye, is the conception of personhood held in such a communitarian
socio-ethical philosophy? Responding to Menkiti’s theses, Gyekye criticizes
them by invoking many Akan thoughts and belief systems, and from thence, draws
his own views which I consider more candid and tenable.
But
to begin with, Gyekye clarifies what ought to be the relationship between the
community and the person vis-à-vis priority. He opines that obviously, the
individual human being is born into an existing human community, and therefore
into a human culture. But also, a community crucially consists of persons
sharing interests and values, and so, emerges with the congregation of
individual persons. This suggests, very appositely, that the human community is
a product of the individual and not vice versa. The individual is therefore
prior to the community, and the community existentially derives from
individuals and the relationships that would exist between them. Moving
further, Gyekye argues that the fact that a person is born into an existing
community must suggest a conception of the person as a communitarian being by
nature, but also, a person is a social or communal being by nature and is also
other things by nature as well (that is, he possesses other essential
attributes like rationality, capable of choice and moral judgement and so on).
Failure to recognize this would confer on the community, a pseudo-all-engulfing
moral authority to determine all things about the life of the individual
person.
Owing from the demonstration of the above, Gyekye then
worthily expresses a profound discountenance for Menkiti’s attempt to prove
that African thought considers personhood as something defined and conferred by
the community and as something that must be acquired by the individual. He does
this by debunking the arguments put forward by Menkiti in support of this
claim. And if these arguments are the basis of Menkiti’s theses and Gyekye
shows these arguments to be untenable and lacking affective praxis, then, they
cannot hold and are false. What are Gyekye’s critiques?
The
first is the ‘It’ critique. Here, Gyekye argues that the way the neuter pronoun
‘It’ functions in English differs from how it functions in some African
languages. Citing the Akan language, ‘it’ does not exist for animate things but
for inanimate things or objects. Citing also the Ga-Dangme language in Ghana,
‘it’ is gender neutral and applies to both animate and inanimate things. On
this note, says Gyekye, Menkiti errs.
The
second is the ‘grief’ critique. Here, Gyekye denies that every older person who
dies in every African community is given elaborate burial. According to him,
the type of the burial and nature and extent of the grief expressed over the
death of an older person depends on the community’s assessment based on the
person’s achievements in life, his/her contribution to the welfare of the
community and the respect he/she commanded in the community. Older persons who
do not satisfy these criteria are given simple and poor funerals and attenuated
forms of grief expressions. As to the absence of ritualized grief on the death
of a child, the reason is not personhood, but beliefs about its possible
consequences. For the Akans, they believe that excessive demonstration of grief
in the event of the death of a child will make the mother infertile by reaching
her menopause prematurely, or, will also drive the dead child too far away for
it to reincarnate, so be reborn. On this note too, Menkiti is amiss.
Thus,
for Gyekye, based on the above, contra
Menkiti, a human person is a person regardless of age or social status.
Personhood may reach its full realization in the community, but it is not
acquired or yet to be achieved as one goes along in the society.
Furthermore,
for Gyekye too, one character of a human person is that a human person (at
least in Akan thought) is a being who has a moral sense and is capable of
making moral judgements. This conception quite includes children and infants.
This is because, according to Gyekye, children (although not actually) are
potentially capable of exercising moral sense and making moral judgements. To the
mentally deranged, if I am to add following Gyekye’s thought pattern, their own
capacity is not absent but in a state of abeyance.
Moral capacity then, is not implanted or conferred by
the community. The community could at best nurture these capacities.
Furthermore,
in the communal setting of the African life, striving for the demonstration of
a sense of personal responsibility, to achieve some measure of success in life
and have a family, are strivings for the attainment of social status not
personhood. These strivings are in fact part of the individual’s exercise of a
capacity he /she has as a person. And even if he/she fails in this striving,
personhood is not diminished though social status or respect might be lost.
Thus, contra Menkiti, it is social
status not personhood that individuals could fail.
More
so, individual persons are rational and capable of choice and so may find
aspects of cultural givens inelegant, obsolete, undignifying or unenlightening,
and thus, thoughtfully question and evaluate them. This may include
affirmation, amendation, refinement or even total rejection of these canons.
On
the whole, for Gyekye, human beings besides being communal by nature, are also
other things as well, like, rationality, capacity for virtue, capacity for
evaluating and making moral judgements and hence, capable of choice. The
community only nurtures and discovers these not creating them.
MY
LOVE FOR GYKEYE
I find Gyekye’s views more
tenable and plausible because they make a point that I consider sacred and
inviolable to me which is that, with Gyekye’s views, the assertion of the
naturality and inviolability of human rights is assured. With this view, it
becomes evident, following Joseph Ratzinger in Values in a Time of Upheaval, that human rights are unconditional
values which are inviolable, sacred and must be protected unconditionally. They
derive from the essence of what it is to be human, are antecedent to any
political arrangement, and are neither defined by a legislator nor given to
human beings. It is something we possess naturally and antecedently. The
community cannot define this for us but nurture it.
Comments
Post a Comment