phenomenological directness
Thesis Statement
The question of how to best capture or
explain the distinctive phenomenology of perceptual experience and how to
develop a theory of perception that explains the phenomenological directness of
perceptual experience and other perceptual experiences like illusion and most
especially hallucination, has been a major difficulty.
Development of Thesis
Two theories made significant efforts to
explain the phenomenological directness of experience, along with all other
forms of perceptual experiences. These theories include, naive realism and the
representational or content view. The naive realism or relational view is the
view that to perceive is to stand in a primitive relation of awareness or
acquaintance to the world. Acquaintance with a property of some particular
object requires that the relevant property is instantiated by that object. While
the content theorist claims that, just as a true belief is true in virtue of
the fact that the proposition that constitutes its content is true, a veridical
perceptual experience is veridical in virtue of the fact that the proposition
that constitutes its content is true. When the proposition that constitutes the
content of a given perceptual experience is false, the relevant experience is
an illusion or hallucination.
There is a problem with the naive
realist’s story regarding why perceptual experiences possess their distinctive
phenomenology and why it can’t explain the phenomenological directness of
illusions and hallucinations. For when I suffer an illusion, a property of some
object seems to be immediately present to me even though it is not instantiated
by that object. But the perceptual acquaintance still cannot explain the
phenomenological directness of such an experience since perceptual acquaintance
with a property of some particular object requires that the relevant property
is instantiated by that object. And when I suffer a hallucination, some object
seems be immediately present to me even though there is no such object—but
perceptual acquaintance can’t explain the phenomenological directness of such
an experience since one can only be perceptually acquainted with objects that
exist. Thus, naive realism would seem to have difficulty handling what we might
call the phenomenological problem of perception. Hallucinations are
phenomenologically distinct from thinking, imagining, and brute sensation in
the ways just described—that they possess phenomenological directness. There
are at least two powerful reasons for thinking hallucinations possess the
phenomenology at issue. First, hallucinations possess the same phenomenological
directness that veridical experiences possess. unlike consciously thinking or
imagining, it’s as though some object itself seems to be immediately present to
you. In addition, you will find that, unlike a brute sensation, the object that
seems to be immediately present to you seems to be something that exists apart
from your experience of it.
According to naive realist accounts of
phenomenological directness, “perceiving an object is an essential relational
state, of which the object perceived is a constituent; so the perception is
constitutively dependent on the object perceived”. The naive realist who
appeals to the fact that veridical experiences have physical objects as constituents
cannott explain the phenomenological directness of hallucinations since there
is no appropriate object to serve as a constituent of the experience. Boyd
Millar believed that the content theorist might be able to provide an account
of phenomenological directness by appealing to the special nature of the
representational contents that perceptual experiences involve. That is, they can
maintain that perceptual experiences are phenomenologically distinct from
conscious thoughts, imaginings, and brute sensations, not in virtue of
involving a unique attitude, but in virtue of involving unique representational
contents. The most promising approach to identifying what distinguishes
perceptual experiences from other kinds of experiences, Millar holds is to
appeal to the representation of the causal relation between the object of
perception and the perceiver.
Regarding the causal relation between the
object of perception and the perceiver, Searle held that; there is a difference
between the voluntarily formed images we would experience as caused by us and
the visual experience of the house we would experience as caused by something
independent of us. And the differences in the two cases are the causal content
of the two experiences. Specifically, while Searle’s view explains the
phenomenological difference between perceptual experience and imagination, it
cannot explain the phenomenological difference between perceptual experience
and conscious thought. The direct causal content view has two unique features
that are particularly important for present purposes. First, when there is a
causal connection between a conscious thought about (or an episode of
imagining) a particular physical object and that object, that causal connection
always involves the mediation of some distinct experience. Conversely, the
causal connection between a veridical perceptual experience of a given object
and that object never involves the mediation of some distinct experience. Secondly,
a veridical perceptual experience of a given object is only ever caused
automatically (in the sense that the experience could not have been
precipitated and cannot be terminated by the exercise of the subject’s will) by
a causal link to the (approximately) present state of that object. Conversely,
a conscious thought about (or episode of imagining) some particular physical
object is typically under the voluntary control of the subject and does not
require a causal link between that thought and the present state of the object.
When an experience is caused by some physical thing, the causal connection
between them does not first involve the mediation of some distinct experience. And second, the experience is generated
automatically by a causal link to the present state of the relevant physical
thing.
Questions
To what extent is perception
constituently dependent on the perceiver? What determines the explanation
between the object of perception or the perceiver?
Conclusion
The direct causal content view explains
the phenomenological directness of perceptual experiences by appealing to the
representation of a certain specific relation rather than to the representation
of objects as such. As a result, both veridical perceptual experiences and
hallucinations can possess that feature that the direct causal content theorist
claims suffices for phenomenological directness; and thus the present view
provides a unified account of the phenomenological directness of both veridical
and hallucinatory experiences. The direct causal content view is also
straightforwardly compatible with Fregean views where a mode of presentation of
an object rather than the object itself is a constituent of the content of a
perceptual experience. According to the direct causal content view, to have a
perceptual experience is to stand in the perceptually-experiencing-relation to
a specific sort of content, which suffices for phenomenological directness.
Comments
Post a Comment