SHORT NOTES ON Virtue Epistemology, Religious Epistemology, Social Epistemology, Naturalized Epistemology, Feminist Epistemology, Moral Epistemology
SHORT NOTES
Virtue Epistemology:
Virtue
epistemology is a contemporary philosophical approach
to epistemology that stresses the importance of
intellectual, and specifically epistemic virtues. By directing attention on the
knower as agent, virtue epistemology is in part modelled after virtue ethics,
since virtue ethics focuses on moral agents rather than moral acts. Epistemology, as commonly practiced, focuses on the subject’s
beliefs, asking questions like: Are they justified? Are they instances of
knowledge? When it comes to accessing how the subject herself is doing with
regard to the pursuit of truth and the seeking of knowledge, this assessment is
carried out by looking at the epistemic quality of her beliefs. But, virtue
epistemology reverses this order of analysis, placing priority of emphasis on
the subject herself and assessing her epistemic virtues and vices, that is, her
good and bad ways of forming beliefs. For Virtue epistemology then, our
doxastic procedures, that is, our procedures for forming beliefs makes us
epistemically virtuous or vicious.
Taking into account the relevant
desiderata (desired essentials) for belief formation, wherein every belief must
have a warrant would be an example of an epistemic virtue. Whereas, jumping
into conclusions would be an example of an epistemic vice. It is only after we
have determined which ways of forming beliefs are reliable or unreliable; which
ways count as epistemic virtues or vices that we can, as a second step,
determine the epistemic quality of particular beliefs.
Religious Epistemology:
In the history of philosophy, there abounds a plethora
of arguments for the existence of God, ranging from the cosmological argument
to the ontological argument and even the argument from design. From an
epistemological point of view, the question is whether such arguments can
constitute a rational foundation of faith, or even afford us knowledge of God.
A further question is whether, if God exists, knowledge of God might not also
be possible in other ways, for example, on the basis of perception or perhaps
mystical experiences.
There is also
a famous problem casting doubt on the existence of God: Why, if God is an
omniscient, omnipotent, and benevolent being, is there evil in the world? Here,
the epistemological question is whether, based on this problem, we can know
that God (thus conceived) does not exist.
Another
central issue for religious epistemology is raised by evidentialism.
Evidentialism avers that knowledge requires adequate evidence. However, there
does not seem to abound any adequate evidence of God’s evidence. Does this,
then, make it possible for theists to endorse evidentialism? The answer is
obviously No. This is because the kind of evidence intended for the knowledge
of God is not sensual but one afforded in the form of premises from which one may
infer theistic conclusions.
Social Epistemology:
Social epistemology is the study of the social
dimension or determinants of knowledge, or the ways in which social factors
promote or perturb the quest for knowledge. When we conceive of epistemology as
including knowledge and justified belief as they are positioned within a
particular social and historical context, epistemology becomes social
epistemology. Some writers use the term ‘knowledge’ loosely, as designating
mere belief. On their view, social epistemology should simply describe how
social factors influence beliefs, without concern for the rationality or truth
of these beliefs.
How to pursue social epistemology is a matter of controversy. According
to some, it is an extension or re-orientation of traditional epistemology with
the aim of correcting its overly individualistic orientation. According to
others, social epistemology ought to amount to a radical departure from
traditional epistemology, which they see, like the advocates of radical
naturalization, as a futile endeavour.
Naturalized Epistemology:
The concept of naturalized epistemology is the brain-child of W.V.O.
Quine. For
Quine, naturalised epistemology is the patterning of the epistemological
pursuit after the methodology and spirit of science. Our epistemological
enquiry in this new setting, Quine argues, is to be concerned not with
providing exemplars for science, but with basing our construction or projection
of the external world based on the interaction between inputs from stimulations
on our sensory surfaces and inputs arising from our conceptual sovereignty.
Here, epistemology is fixed in a new setting as a component of natural science
and as a chapter of psychology. Quine says that our object in this new setting
of epistemology is “studying how the human subject of our study posits bodies
and projects his physics from his data…” He further says in another place that,
“our liberated epistemologist ends up as an empirical psychologist,
scientifically investigating man’s acquisition of science.”
In naturalising
epistemology, Quine maintains that epistemology in the new setting becomes
enlightened because it no longer seeks solution to the sceptics’ challenge
outside science but realises that the sceptics’ challenge springs from science
itself, and that in coping with it, we are free to use scientific knowledge.
Quine sees philosophy and science in the same boat, a boat which like Neurath’s
boat, we could rebuild only at sea while staying afloat in it.
Epistemology
therefore for Quine, can make progress by adopting the scientific attitude of
continually rebuilding the framework of its conjectures and refutations on the
platform of sense experience (observation sentence) and theory. Quine’s
proposal is human, speculative, not feigning the impossible and pragmatic. In
fact, for Quine, naturalised epistemology is one in which the epistemic
enterprise takes cognisance of the limited powers of the human agent, focusing
then on what can be known not what we ought to know. Since, as Quine avers, it
is useless to seek to reach objective truths about reality because it is
impossible. The ‘ought’ then, as Quine thinks, should always imply ‘can’ in our
epistemological objectives so that we do not end up recommending procedures
that cognizers cannot attain.
Feminist
Epistemology:
Feminist epistemology
is one that investigates the relevance that the gender of the knower has to
epistemic practices, including the theoretical practice of epistemology. It is
typified both by themes that are exclusively feminist in that they could arise
from a critical attention to gender, and by themes that are non-exclusively
feminist in that they might arise from other politicizing theoretical
perspectives besides feminism.
When
construed in a non-controversial way, the subject matter of feminist
epistemology consists of issues having to do with fair and equal access of
women to, and their participation in, the institutions and processes through
which knowledge is generated and transmitted. Viewed in this way, feminist
epistemology can be seen as a branch of social epistemology.
When
we move beyond this initial characterization, feminist epistemology becomes
controversial. For some, its aim includes the project of studying and
legitimizing special ways in which women can acquire knowledge. For others,
feminist epistemology should be understood as aiming at the political goal of
opposing and rectifying oppression in general and the oppression of women in
particular. At the extreme end, feminist epistemology is closely associated
with postmodernism and its radical attack on truth and the notion of objective
reality. It also represents a radicalizing innovation in the analytic
tradition, which has typically assumed on a social conception of knowledge.
Moral
Epistemology:
This is a
discipline, at the intersection of ethics and epistemology, that studies the
epistemic status and relations of moral judgements and principles. It developed
out of an interest common to both ethics and epistemology, in questions of
justification and justifiability in epistemology, of statements or beliefs, and
in ethics, of actions as well as judgements of action and also general
principles of judgement. Its most prominent questions include the following:
Can normative claims be true or false? If so, how can they be known to be true
or false? If not, what status do they have, and are they capable of
justification? If they are capable of justification, how can they be justified?
Does the justification of normative claims differ with respect to particular
claims and with respect to general principles?
Comments
Post a Comment