SHORT NOTES
EXAM: SHORT NOTES
Virtue Epistemology:
Virtue
epistemology is a contemporary philosophical approach
to epistemology that
stresses the importance of intellectual, and specifically epistemic virtues. By directing attention on the
knower as agent, virtue epistemology is in part modelled after virtue ethics,
since virtue ethics focuses on moral agents rather than moral acts. Epistemology, as commonly practiced, focuses on the subject’s
beliefs, asking questions like: Are they justified? Are they instances of
knowledge? When it comes to accessing how the subject herself is doing with
regard to the pursuit of truth and the seeking of knowledge, this assessment is
carried out by looking at the epistemic quality of her beliefs. But, virtue
epistemology reverses this order of analysis, placing priority of emphasis on
the subject herself and assessing her epistemic virtues and vices, that is, her
good and bad ways of forming beliefs. For Virtue epistemology then, our
doxastic procedures, that is, our procedures for forming beliefs makes us
epistemically virtuous or vicious.
Taking into account the relevant
desiderata (desired essentials) for belief formation, wherein every belief must
have a warrant would be an example of an epistemic virtue. Whereas, jumping
into conclusions would be an example of an epistemic vice. It is only after we
have determined which ways of forming beliefs are reliable or unreliable; which
ways count as epistemic virtues or vices that we can, as a second step,
determine the epistemic quality of particular beliefs.
Religious Epistemology:
In the history of philosophy, there abounds a plethora
of arguments for the existence of God, ranging from the cosmological argument
to the ontological argument and even the argument from design. From an
epistemological point of view, the question is whether such arguments can
constitute a rational foundation of faith, or even afford us knowledge of God.
A further question is whether, if God exists, knowledge of God might not also
be possible in other ways, for example, on the basis of perception or perhaps
mystical experiences.
There is also a
famous problem casting doubt on the existence of God: Why, if God is an
omniscient, omnipotent, and benevolent being, is there evil in the world? Here,
the epistemological question is whether, based on this problem, we can know
that God (thus conceived) does not exist.
Another central
issue for religious epistemology is raised by evidentialism. Evidentialism
avers that knowledge requires adequate evidence. However, there does not seem
to abound any adequate evidence of God’s evidence. Does this, then, make it
possible for theists to endorse evidentialism? The answer is obviously No. This
is because the kind of evidence intended for the knowledge of God is not
sensual but one afforded in the form of premises from which one may infer
theistic conclusions.
Social Epistemology:
Social epistemology is the study of the social
dimension or determinants of knowledge, or the ways in which social factors
promote or perturb the quest for knowledge. When we conceive of epistemology as
including knowledge and justified belief as they are positioned within a
particular social and historical context, epistemology becomes social
epistemology. Some writers use the term ‘knowledge’ loosely, as designating
mere belief. On their view, social epistemology should simply describe how
social factors influence beliefs, without concern for the rationality or truth
of these beliefs.
How to pursue social epistemology is a matter of controversy. According
to some, it is an extension or re-orientation of traditional epistemology with
the aim of correcting its overly individualistic orientation. According to
others, social epistemology ought to amount to a radical departure from
traditional epistemology, which they see, like the advocates of radical
naturalization, as a futile endeavour.
Naturalized Epistemology:
The concept of naturalized epistemology is the brain-child of W.V.O.
Quine. For Quine,
naturalised epistemology is the patterning of the epistemological pursuit after
the methodology and spirit of science. Our epistemological enquiry in this new
setting, Quine argues, is to be concerned not with providing exemplars for
science, but with basing our construction or projection of the external world
based on the interaction between inputs from stimulations on our sensory
surfaces and inputs arising from our conceptual sovereignty. Here, epistemology
is fixed in a new setting as a component of natural science and as a chapter of
psychology. Quine says that our object in this new setting of epistemology is
“studying how the human subject of our study posits bodies and projects his
physics from his data…” He further says in another place that, “our liberated
epistemologist ends up as an empirical psychologist, scientifically
investigating man’s acquisition of science.”
In naturalising epistemology, Quine
maintains that epistemology in the new setting becomes enlightened because it
no longer seeks solution to the sceptics’ challenge outside science but
realises that the sceptics’ challenge springs from science itself, and that in
coping with it, we are free to use scientific knowledge. Quine sees philosophy
and science in the same boat, a boat which like Neurath’s boat, we could
rebuild only at sea while staying afloat in it.
Epistemology therefore for Quine,
can make progress by adopting the scientific attitude of continually rebuilding
the framework of its conjectures and refutations on the platform of sense
experience (observation sentence) and theory. Quine’s proposal is human,
speculative, not feigning the impossible and pragmatic. In fact, for Quine,
naturalised epistemology is one in which the epistemic enterprise takes
cognisance of the limited powers of the human agent, focusing then on what can
be known not what we ought to know. Since, as Quine avers, it is useless to
seek to reach objective truths about reality because it is impossible. The
‘ought’ then, as Quine thinks, should always imply ‘can’ in our epistemological
objectives so that we do not end up recommending procedures that cognizers
cannot attain.
Feminist
Epistemology:
Feminist epistemology is one that
investigates the relevance that the gender of the knower has to epistemic
practices, including the theoretical practice of epistemology. It is typified
both by themes that are exclusively feminist in that they could arise from a
critical attention to gender, and by themes that are non-exclusively feminist
in that they might arise from other politicizing theoretical perspectives
besides feminism.
When construed in a
non-controversial way, the subject matter of feminist epistemology consists of
issues having to do with fair and equal access of women to, and their
participation in, the institutions and processes through which knowledge is
generated and transmitted. Viewed in this way, feminist epistemology can be
seen as a branch of social epistemology.
When we move beyond this initial
characterization, feminist epistemology becomes controversial. For some, its
aim includes the project of studying and legitimizing special ways in which
women can acquire knowledge. For others, feminist epistemology should be
understood as aiming at the political goal of opposing and rectifying oppression
in general and the oppression of women in particular. At the extreme end,
feminist epistemology is closely associated with postmodernism and its radical
attack on truth and the notion of objective reality. It also represents a
radicalizing innovation in the analytic tradition, which has typically assumed
on a social conception of knowledge.
Moral
Epistemology:
This is a discipline, at the
intersection of ethics and epistemology, that studies the epistemic status and
relations of moral judgements and principles. It developed out of an interest
common to both ethics and epistemology, in questions of justification and
justifiability in epistemology, of statements or beliefs, and in ethics, of
actions as well as judgements of action and also general principles of
judgement. Its most prominent questions include the following: Can normative
claims be true or false? If so, how can they be known to be true or false? If
not, what status do they have, and are they capable of justification? If they
are capable of justification, how can they be justified? Does the justification
of normative claims differ with respect to particular claims and with respect
to general principles?
Comments
Post a Comment