THE RIGHT TO SELF TERMINATION


Introduction

Throughout history, suicide has evoked an astonishingly wide range of reactions—bafflement, dismissal, heroic glorification, sympathy, anger, moral or religious condemnation—but it is never uncontroversial. Suicide is now an object of multidisciplinary scientific study, with sociology, anthropology, psychology, and psychiatry each providing important insights into suicide. Nonetheless, many of the most controversial questions surrounding suicide are philosophical. For philosophers, suicide raises a host of conceptual, moral, and psychological questions. Among these questions are: What makes a person’s behaviour suicidal? What motivates such behaviour? Is suicide morally permissible, or even morally required in some extraordinary circumstances? Is suicidal behaviour rational? [1] This paper shall discuss in details, what suicide is, the historical reflection of suicide, the different stands of various philosophers and schools of thought regarding suicide, then will finally move to the primary article, the right of self-termination, by Velleman, before giving a final conclusion.

Definition Of Suicide

Suicide is the act of one taking his/her own life, voluntarily and deliberately.[2] It is an action which the doer does to bring about his/her own death.[3] Suicide is an attempt to inflict death upon oneself and is intentional rather than consequential in nature.[4]

The History Of Reflection Of Suicide

The western record of discussion and dispute about the morality of suicide began almost four millennia ago with a rather personal dialogue between a man and his soul, a dialogue dating from the middle kingdom of ancient Egypt. Writing on suicide continues with the early Hebrew texts that record- without ethical comment- a handful of figures who caused their own deaths, among them Samson (who pulled the temple down upon himself, as well as the philistines), Saul, and Saul’s armour bearer. [5]
In a different culture, ancient Greece, Socrates was of the view that we are put in a sort of guard post, from which we must not release our self or run away. The gods are our keepers, and we are their possessions. It is unreasonable that we put an end to ourselves until the gods sends death.[6] 
Plato developed a somewhat inchoate classification of acceptable and unacceptable suicides, including those subject to burial restrictions and those that were not. [7] Plato claimed that suicide is disgraceful and its perpetrators should be solitary; they must have no companions whatsoever in the tomb. Further, they must be buried ignominiously in a waste and nameless spots, and the tomb shall be marked by neither headstone nor name. [8] Later, in the Laws, He gave four exemptions:
·         when one’s mind is morally corrupted and one’s character can therefore not be salvaged (Laws IX 854a3–5)[9]
·         when the self-killing is done by judicial order, as in the case of Socrates
·         when the self-killing is compelled by extreme and unavoidable personal misfortune
·         when the self-killing results from shame at having participated in grossly unjust actions (Laws IX 873c-d).[10]
Suicide under these circumstances can be excused, but, according to Plato, it is otherwise an act of cowardice or laziness undertaken by individuals too delicate to manage life’s vicissitudes..[11]
Aristotle took suicide generally to damage the state. Aristotle reinforced the platonic prohibition against suicide, asserting that man belongs not to himself but to the gods and the state. In the Nicomachean ethics, he writes:
The law does not expressly permit suicide, and what it does not expressly permit it forbids… he who through anger voluntarily stabs himself does this contrary to the right rule of life, and this the law does not allow; therefore he is acting unjustly. But towards whom? Surely towards the state, not towards himself. For he suffers voluntarily, but no one is voluntarily treated unjustly. This is also the reason why the state punishes; a certain loss of civil rights attaches to the man who destroys himself, on the ground that he is treating the state unjustly. [12]
Herodotus wrote: "When life is so burdensome, death has become for man a sought-after refuge". Schopenhauer affirmed: "They tell us that suicide is the greatest act of cowardice... that suicide is wrong; when it is quite obvious that there is nothing in the world to which every man has a more unassailable title than to his own life and person."[13]
Schopenhauer denied that suicide was immoral and saw it as one's right to take one's life. In an allegory, he compared ending one's life, when subject to great suffering, to waking up from sleep when experiencing a terrible nightmare. However, most suicides were seen as an act of the will, as it takes place when one denies life's pains, and is thus different from ascetic renunciation of the will, which denies life's pleasures.[14]
In the following centuries, the Greek and Roman Stoic came to celebrate suicide as the act of the wise man, while the Christian church fathers, like the Jewish rabbis, though developing teaching that celebrated martyrdom, at the same time increasingly vigorously condemned suicide as sin. [15]
Scripture writers recount several instances of justifiable self-killing. Saul, the first king of Israel, kills himself after the philistines defeat his army, kill his sons, and wound him: “therefore Saul took a sword, and fell upon it. “in the case of Samson’s suicide, also occasioned by defeat, the motive is revenge. In the biblical Jewish thought, as in Greco-Roman thought, self-killing in the interest of divine will is morally justified.[16]
Roman law expanded the criteria that made suicide morally acceptable. For example, when one feels he has had enough of life; was a justification for suicide. However, roman law prohibited the suicide of slaves, because they destroyed not themselves but their masters’ property; and of defendants accused of crime, because their deed prevented the law from determining whether they were guilty or not. If their deed was interpreted as signifying guilt, the law required that their corpse be denied ritual burial and their property be confiscated. Christians cannon law adopted the practice of denying religious burial to the suicide’s corpse, and medieval English criminal law reinstated the penalty of forfeiting the suicides property. [17]
Christian doctrine has by and large held that suicide is morally wrong, despite the absence of clear Scriptural guidance regarding suicide. the early church fathers opposed suicide, St. Augustine is generally credited with offering the first justification of the Christian prohibition on suicide. He saw the prohibition as a natural extension of the fifth commandment: [18]
St. Thomas Aquinas later defended this prohibition on three grounds.
·         Suicide is contrary to natural self-love, whose aim is to preserve us.
·         Suicide injures the community of which an individual is a part.
·         Suicide violates our duty to God because God has given us life as a gift and in taking our lives we violate His right to determine the duration of our earthly existence. [19]

Schools Of Thought

Liberialism

Libertarians typically believe that we have a natural right of self-ownership[20] they asserts that one's life belongs only to himself, and no other person has the right to force their own ideals that life must be lived. Rather, only the individual involved can make such a decision, and whatever decision he make should be respected.[21]
A popular basis supporting a right to suicide is the idea that we own our bodies and hence are morally permitted to dispose of them as we wish. On this view, our relationship to our bodies is like that of our relationship to other items over which we enjoy property rights: Just as our having a right to a wristwatch permits us to use, improve, and dispose of it as we wish, so too does our having a right to our bodies permit us to dispose of them as we see fit. Consequently, since property rights are exclusive (i.e., our having property rights to a thing prohibits others from interfering with it), others may not interfere with our efforts to end our lives. [22]
Thomas Szasz goes further, arguing that suicide is the most basic right of all. If freedom is self-ownership—ownership over one's own life and body—then the right to end that life is the most basic of all. If others can force you to live, you do not own yourself and belong to them.[23]
Stoicism
most famous stoicsSeneca the YoungerEpictetus, and Marcus Aurelius—maintain that death by one's own hand is always an option and frequently more honorable than a life of protracted misery.[24] the Stoics held that whenever the means to living a naturally flourishing life are not available to us, suicide may be justified, regardless of the character or virtue of the individual in question. Our natures require certain “natural advantages” (e.g., physical health) in order for us to be happy, and a wise person who recognizes that such advantages may be lacking in her life sees that ending her life neither enhances nor diminishes her moral virtue.[25]
The Stoics accepted that suicide is permissible for the wise person in circumstances that might prevent them from living a virtuous life.  Suicide could be justified if one falls victim to severe pain or disease, but otherwise suicide would usually be seen as a rejection of one's social duty.[26] Consequentialism
The consequentialist framework looks to the potential consequences of suicide to determine whether it is forbidden, permissible or obliged.[27]

Deontology

Deontology is of the view that suicide is necessarily wrong because human life is sacred. According to this ‘sanctity of life’ view, human life is inherently valuable and precious, demanding respect from others and reverence for oneself. Hence, suicide is wrong because it violates our moral duty to honor the inherent value of human life, regardless of the value of that life to others or to the person whose life it is. The sanctity of life view is thus a deontological position on suicide. [28]

CONCEPT OF SUICIDE BY DAVID VELLEMAN, IN THE RIGHT TO SELF TERMINATION.
J. David Velleman is a professor of philosophy at New York university. He primary works in the areas of ethics, moral psychology, and related areas such as the philosophy of action, and practical reasoning. He is a co-editor with Stephen Darwall of Philosophers imprint, an on-line, peer-refereed philosophy journal. He wrote classically on suicide in his work, The Right To Self-Termination.

Do We Have The Right To Self-Termination

David Velleman painted an imagery of one who is suffering from cancer. The pain and sorrows he goes through, which obviously only him can feel. This he did to show that one has a better knowledge of his life.[29] The claim of the right to live or die he mentioned, lies in ones convictions about why his/her life is valuable and where its value lies.[30]

There are two principles velleman believe which would settle the issue which concerns whether we have the right to self-termination or not. First; that a person has the right to make his own life shorter in order to make it better, that is if doing so is a necessary means or consequence of making it a better life on the whole for him, and secondly, that there is a presumption in favour of deferring to a person’s judgment on the subject of his own good. Together, these principles imply that a person has the right to live and die, in particular, by his own convictions about which life would be better for him.[31]
In most of the cases for which assisted suicide is advocated, shortening a patient's life is intended as a means of making it better, because the continuation of the patient's life would detract from its overall value for him. This is in accordance with the first principle mentioned earlier, the assertion of a patient's right to end his life on the grounds that it is no longer worth living. Velleman rejected this first principle, and sees it as mistaken, while he accepted the second principle. He is of the view that we generally ought to defer to a person on the question whether his life is worth living, since the living worthiness of a life measures the extent to which the continuation of that life would be good for the person living it. The person living a life is the best judge of the value that its continuation would afford him, but not an infallible judge, but usually more reliable than anyone else. Indeed, his judgment of this value is to some extent self-fulfilling, since his merely liking or disliking aspects of his life can to some extent make them good or bad for him.[32]
The reasons for deferring to a person's judgment about his good velleman held, goes beyond his reliability as a judge. Respect for a person's autonomy may require that we defer to his considered judgment about his good even when we have reason to regard that judgment as mistaken. Letting him live his own life may sometimes entail letting him make his own mistakes about what's good for him-including, perhaps, mistakes about whether it would be good for him to go on living. Forbidding a person to make such mistakes can be objectionably paternalistic, because it would usurp his role as the primary agent of his own affairs.[33]
Thus, if a person had the right to end his life on the grounds that it wasn't worth living (in accordance with the first principle, above), then he would have the right to be guided by his own judgment on that score (in accordance with the second principle).
Velleman reject the principle that a person has the right to end his life solely on the grounds of the benefits he will thereby obtain or the harms he will avoid. One reason for rejecting this principle is that a life confers benefits and harms on people other than the person living it. Does a person have the right to deprive his children of a parent simply because life isn't worth enough to him? [34]

Dignity Of Human Person In The Kantian Perspective

The great german philosopher Immanuel kant thought that human beings occupy a special place in creation.[35]Kant’s concept of human dignity designates a value that has no equivalent- i.e. that which is beyond price.[36] A value of this kind, which a person has in himself but not for anyone, is the basis of Kantian moral theory. Kant's term for this value is 'dignity', and he attributes dignity to all persons in virtue of their rational nature.
What morality requires of us, according to Kant, is that we respect the dignity of persons. The dignity of a person is a value that differs in kind from his interest. Unlike his interest, for example, his dignity is a value on which his opinion carries no more weight than anyone else's. Because this value does not accrue to him, he is in no better position to judge it than others. Similarly, respect for a person's autonomy does not require deference to him on questions of his dignity, as it does on questions of his good. On the contrary, respect for a person's autonomy just is an appreciation of a value in him that amounts to a dignity, in Kant's sense of the term, precisely because it commands respect. If a person denies embodying such a value, he can hardly claim that we should defer to him out of an appreciation for a value such as he denies. He cannot claim, in other words, that out of respect for his autonomy we should defer to his judgment that he possesses nothing worthy of our respect. Nor is it paternalistic to challenge a person's judgment about his dignity, as it is in the case of his good. Challenging a person's judgment about his good is objectionable because it undermines his role as the agent of his own affairs; but his value as a person is not just his affair. Although his good is a value that accrues to him alone, in the first instance, his value as a person inheres in him among other persons. It's a value that he possesses by virtue of being one of us, and the value of being one of us is not his alone to assess or defend. The value of being  a person is therefore something larger than any particular person who embodies it. That's what If a patient decides to die, he is waiving his right to live. By waiving his right, he releases others (perhaps a specific other person) from a duty not to kill him.[37]
This can't be right. It portrays morality as protecting a person's options without protecting the person himself, except insofar as his own existence is one of his options. Surely, however, options are worth protecting, not for their own sake, but for the sake of the person whose options they are.[38]

Are People Morally Permitted To End Their Existence Solely Because They Find It Unrewarding

Francis Kamm is of the view that when life involves such unbearable pain that one’s whole life is focused on that pain, in such circumstance, one could decline the honour of being a person. The great value of being a person may be acknowledged, and yet allow that some bad conditions may overshadow its very great value[39]
Hill thinks that even a Kantian could embrace the permissibility of suicide in specific cases. He mentions three
·         where one’s future life will involve a complete loss of rational autonomy due to some degenerative disorder (rational autonomy being an essential precondition for Kantian moral reasoning)
·         where it helps to avoid gross irremediable pain
·         where it is the only way to avoid a future that is degrading and contrary to one’s deepest values.[40]

Kant was right according to velleman, to say that trading one's person in exchange for benefits, or relief from harms, denigrates the value of personhood, respect for which is a criterion of morality. It's in that regards velleman held that suicide is immoral when committed on the grounds that life isn't worth living.[41]
Regarding the question of if people are morally permitted to end their existence solely because they find it unrewarding; velleman held that people are not morally permitted to end their existence, on the ground that they would be violating their own interest-independent value as persons. One’s death cannot be justified on the grounds that its good for him, while also denying the existence of another value, embodied in him.[42]
The idea that dignity can justify a person's death may seem incompatible with the Kantian conception of dignity as a value inhering in the person. Dignity is what Kant called a "self-existent" a value to which we are obliged to respond only when it already exists, and then only by paying it reverence or respect. The value of persons does not oblige us to maximize the number of people in existence; it obliges us only to respect the people who do exist. And respecting these people is not necessarily a matter of keeping them in existence; it is rather a matter of treating them in the way that is required by their personhood-whatever way that is.  The Kantian objection to suicide, then, is not that it destroys something of value. The objection is not even to suicide per se, but to suicide committed for a particular kind of reason-that is, in order to obtain benefits or escape harms. And the objection to suicide committed for this reason is that it denigrates the person's dignity, by trading his person for interest-relative goods, as if it were one of them. This interpretation of the objection to suicide leaves open the possibility that a person's dignity may justify suicide in other contexts, if suicide would constitute an appropriate expression of respect for one's person. Kantianism would then be able to endorse the notion of dying with dignity.[43]
Actually, the phrase 'dying with dignity' is potentially misleading. Velleman held that a person's death is not morally acceptable if he can carry it off with dignity. Rather, a person's death is acceptable if he can no longer live with dignity. The operative concept is undignified life, not dignified death. When a person cannot sustain both life and dignity, his death may indeed be morally justified.[44]

What Constitutes The Loss Of Dignity For A Person.

The dignity in question has nothing to do with being dignified, with keeping up appearances, or with sustaining any particular social status. It has nothing to do with what people ought to admire or esteem in one another, or with what they actually respect. It is rather what they ought to respect, in the way that they can manifest only by treating one another morally. According to Kant, what people ought to respect in this way is one another's rational nature.[45]
Kant's view is borne out by Kamm's example, in which "life involves such unbearable pain that one's whole life is focused on that pain." Kamm assumes that this case invites us to weigh the disvalue of pain against the value of being a rational agent. Kamm described a case in which pain is more than painful, since it not only hurts the patient but also becomes the sole focus of his life. Pain that tyrannizes the patient in this fashion undermines his rational agency, by preventing him from choosing any ends for himself other than relief. It reduces the patient to the psychological hedonist's image of a person-a pleasure-seeking, pain-fleeing animal-which is undignified indeed. And Kamm is clearly envisioning that this severely reduced condition of the patient can be ended only by his death.[46]
Velleman held, then, that if euthanasia seems justified in Kamm's example, the reason is not that relieving the patient's pain is more important than his dignity as a person; rather, that pain has already undermined the patient's dignity, and irretrievably so. The example thus supports dying for the sake of dignity, not for the sake of self-interest.[47]


Conclusion

To find pain unbearable is to find it thus destructive not just of one's well-being but of oneself.
a patient in unbearable pain is no longer his rational old self. If his pain is truly unbearable, then he isn't his rational self any longer: he is falling apart in pain. Suicide can only be justified, if , and only if, it is an Kamm calls it, unbearable. What justifies death is the unbearableness of the pain rather than the painfulness.

REFERENCE
John Danaher, Philosophical Disquisitions. The Ethics Of Suicide: A Framework. http://philosophicaldisquisitions.blogspot.com.ng/2014/05/the-ethics-of-suicide-framework.html
Aristotle Trans. Nicomachean Ethics W. D. Ross,
Cholbi, , M., “Kant and the Irrationality of Suicide”, History of Philosophy Quarterly, 17(2): 159–176. 2000
Durkheim, E., 1897, Le Suicide, Paris: G. Baillière.
Ed. Margaret Paabst Battin, The Ethics Of Suicide: Historical Sources. (New York: Oxford University Press, 2015) Pg 3
Fairbairn, G., 1995, Contemplating Suicide: The Language and Ethics of Self-Harm, London: Routledge.
Human dignity and bioethics: Essays Commisioned by the president’s council on Bioethics. https://bioethicsarchive.georgetown.edu/pcbe/reports/human_dignity/chapter13.html
J. David Velleman, A Right of Self-Termination? Ethics, Vol.109,No.3. (Chicago: Chicago University Press, Apr.,1999).606
James Rachels, Kantian Theory: The Idea Of Human Dignity. January 1990. https://www.google.com.ng/amp/s/www.researchgate.net/publication/262159263_Kantian_theory_the_idea_of_human_dignity/amp
John Danaher, Philosophical Disquisitions. The Ethics Of Suicide: A Framework. http://philosophicaldisquisitions.blogspot.com.ng/2014/05/the-ethics-of-suicide-framework.html
Plato, Complete Works, ed. John M. Cooper and D.S. Hutchinson, (Indiana Polis/Cambridge: Hacket Publishing Company, 1997).
Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theological, Vol. 2, Trans. Fathers Of The English Domimican Province (New York: Benziger Brothers, 1925): “Whether It Is Lawful To Kill Oneself”, Part 2, Question 64. P. A5
Thomas Szasz. The Ethics And Politics Of Suicide, Fatal Freedom. (Praega: Syracuse University Press 2002).pg 12
Wikipedia, philosophy of suicide. https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Philosophy_of_suicide



[1] Cholbi, Michael, “Suicide”, the Stanford Enclyclopedia of philosophy (2017 edition), ed Edward N. Zalta.
[2] Page 2
[3] Durkheim, E., 1897, Le Suicide, Paris: G. Baillière.
[4] Fairbairn, G., 1995, Contemplating Suicide: The Language and Ethics of Self-Harm, London: Routledge.
[5] Ed. Margaret Paabst Battin, The Ethics Of Suicide: Historical Sources. (New York: Oxford University Press, 2015) Pg 3
[6] Ed. Margaret Paabst Battin, The Ethics Of Suicide: Historical Sources. (New York: Oxford University Press, 2015) Pg 10
[7] Ed. Margaret Paabst Battin, The Ethics Of Suicide: Historical Sources. (New York: Oxford University Press, 2015) Pg 3
[8] Thomas Szasz. The Ethics And Politics Of Suicide, Fatal Freedom. (Praega: Syracuse University Press 2002).pg 12
[9] Plato, Complete Works, ed. John M. Cooper and D.S. Hutchinson, (Indiana Polis/Cambridge: Hacket Publishing Company, 1997).
[10] Plato, Complete Works, ed. John M. Cooper and D.S. Hutchinson, (Indiana Polis/Cambridge: Hacket Publishing Company, 1997).
[11] Cholbi, Michael, “Suicide”, the Stanford Enclyclopedia of philosophy (2017 edition), ed Edward N. Zalta.
[12] Aristotle Trans. Nicomachean Ethics W. D. Ross,
[15] Ed. Margaret Paabst Battin, The Ethics Of Suicide: Historical Sources. (New York: Oxford University Press, 2015) Pg 3
[16] Thomas Szasz. The Ethics And Politics Of Suicide, Fatal Freedom. (Praega: Syracuse University Press 2002).pg 12
[17] Thomas Szasz. The Ethics And Politics Of Suicide, Fatal Freedom. (Praega: Syracuse University Press 2002).pg 12
[18] Cholbi, Michael, “Suicide”, the Stanford Enclyclopedia of philosophy (2017 edition), ed Edward N. Zalta.
[19] Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theological, Vol. 2, Trans. Fathers Of The English Domimican Province (New York: Benziger Brothers, 1925): “Whether It Is Lawful To Kill Oneself”, Part 2, Question 64. P. A5
[20]  John Danaher, Philosophical Disquisitions. The Ethics Of Suicide: A Framework. http://philosophicaldisquisitions.blogspot.com.ng/2014/05/the-ethics-of-suicide-framework.html
[22] Cholbi, , M., “Kant and the Irrationality of Suicide”, History of Philosophy Quarterly, 17(2): 159–176. 2000
[24] Wikipedia, philosophy of suicide. https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Philosophy_of_suicide
[25] Cholbi, Michael, “Suicide”, the Stanford Enclyclopedia of philosophy (2017 edition), ed Edward N. Zalta.
[27] John Danaher, Philosophical Disquisitions. The Ethics Of Suicide: A Framework. http://philosophicaldisquisitions.blogspot.com.ng/2014/05/the-ethics-of-suicide-framework.html
[28] Cholbi, Michael, “Suicide”, the Stanford Enclyclopedia of philosophy (2017 edition), ed Edward N. Zalta.
[29] J. David Velleman, A Right of Self-Termination? Ethics, Vol.109,No.3. (Chicago: Chicago University Press, Apr.,1999).606
[30] J. David Velleman, A Right of Self-Termination? Ethics, Vol.109,No.3. (Chicago: Chicago University Press, Apr.,1999). 607
[31] J. David Velleman, A Right of Self-Termination? Ethics, Vol.109,No.3. (Chicago: Chicago University Press, Apr.,1999). 607
[32] J. David Velleman, A Right of Self-Termination? Ethics, Vol.109,No.3. (Chicago: Chicago University Press, Apr.,1999). Pg 608
[33] Ibid.
[34] J. David Velleman, A Right of Self-Termination? Ethics, Vol.109,No.3. (Chicago: Chicago University Press, Apr.,1999). Pg 606
[35] James Rachels, Kantian Theory: The Idea Of Human Dignity. January 1990. https://www.google.com.ng/amp/s/www.researchgate.net/publication/262159263_Kantian_theory_the_idea_of_human_dignity/amp
[36] Human dignity and bioethics: Essays Commisioned by the president’s council on Bioethics. https://bioethicsarchive.georgetown.edu/pcbe/reports/human_dignity/chapter13.html
[37] J. David Velleman, A Right of Self-Termination? Ethics, Vol.109,No.3. (Chicago: Chicago University Press, Apr.,1999). 611-613
[38] J. David Velleman, A Right of Self-Termination? Ethics, Vol.109,No.3. (Chicago: Chicago University Press, Apr.,1999). 612
[39] J. David Velleman, A Right of Self-Termination? Ethics, Vol.109,No.3. (Chicago: Chicago University Press, Apr.,1999). 613
[40] John Danaher, Philosophical Disquisitions. The Ethics Of Suicide: A Framework. http://philosophicaldisquisitions.blogspot.com.ng/2014/05/the-ethics-of-suicide-framework.html
[41] J. David Velleman, A Right of Self-Termination? Ethics, Vol.109,No.3. (Chicago: Chicago University Press, Apr.,1999). 613
[42] J. David Velleman, A Right of Self-Termination? Ethics, Vol.109,No.3. (Chicago: Chicago University Press, Apr.,1999). 615
[43] J. David Velleman, A Right of Self-Termination? Ethics, Vol.109,No.3. (Chicago: Chicago University Press, Apr.,1999). 616
[44] J. David Velleman, A Right of Self-Termination? Ethics, Vol.109,No.3. (Chicago: Chicago University Press, Apr.,1999). 617
[45] ibid
[46] J. David Velleman, A Right of Self-Termination? Ethics, Vol.109,No.3. (Chicago: Chicago University Press, Apr.,1999). Pg. 618
[47] ibid

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

SUMMARY OF PROVIDENTISSIMUS DEUS, ENCYCLICAL LETTER OF POPE LEO XIII ON THE STUDY OF THE HOLY SCRIPTURE.

summary and appraisal of chapters one, two and three of the book The African Origin of Greek Philosophy: An Exercise in Afrocentrism, by Innocent C. Onyewuenyi.

THE LAST THREE WAYS TO PROVES GOD'S EXISTENCE BY THOMAS AQUINAS