TRADITIONAL EPISTEMOLOGY AND GETTIERS PROBLEM.


INTRODUCTION
Man desires to know; he is an inquisitive being. Epistemology as a branch of philosophy, inquires into the nature, limits, and requirements of knowledge. It inquires into what justifies a belief, and what we mean when we say that a claim is true. As it were, there are problems and issues that can be raised about knowledge. First, what does it mean to say that we know the things we claim to know? What conditions must be satisfied for such a claim to be true? Secondly, how do we know the things we claim to know?
Epistemology in the context of Western philosophy is often thought to have begun with Plato, especially in the Theaetetus, where knowledge is first formulated as justified true belief (JTB); but as a self-conscious area of inquiry and as a coherent, developing conversation, it is usually dated from Rene Descartes (Meditations). For the last few years, epistemologists have shifted towards more delimited questions, especially those concerned with problem of justification, the organizational structure of knowledge, the meaning of epistemic terms, and the psychology of belief formation.[1] Edmund Gettier, a contemporary epistemologist is one of such. He challenged the traditional epistemology and formulated a problem that a fallibilistic theory of epistemic justification is possible,[2] and that the traditionalist's conditions are insufficient for knowledge.
This article, therefore, will provide a systematic overview of the problems that the questions above raise and focus in some depth-on issues relating to the structure and the limits of knowledge and justification, especially as proposed by Gettier. Our first task then, would be to explain the term "epistemology," as seen in the traditional sense, i.e as Justified True Belief. Thereafter, we shall examine the Gettier problem, and its corresponding responses. This would, however, lead us to the structure of justification, and finally, the conclusion.
EPISTEMOLOGY
Defined narrowly, epistemology is the study of knowledge and justified belief. As the study of knowledge, epistemology is concerned with the necessary and sufficient conditions of knowledge, its sources, its structure, and its limits. As the study of justified belief, epistemology aims to answer questions such as: How we are to understand the concept of justification? What makes justified beliefs justified? Is justification internal or external to one's own mind?
Understood more broadly, epistemology is about issues having to do with the creation and dissemination of knowledge in particular areas of inquiry. Meanwhile, there are different kinds of knowledge. One is procedural knowledge, sometimes called 'know-how'. Another kind of knowledge is called acquaintance knowledge. However, Epistemology do not focus on procedural or acquaintance knowledge, instead preferring to focus on propositional knowledge. A proposition is something which can be expressed by a declarative sentence and which purports to describe a fact, or a state of affairs, such as "Dogs are mammals" or "It is wrong to murder innocent people for fun."[3] Propositional knowledge then can be called knowledge-that. We can also distinguish different types of Propositional knowledge, based on the source of that knowledge. Non-empirical or a priori knowledge is possible independently of, or prior to any experience, and requires only the use of reason. Empirical or a posteriori knowledge is possible only subsequent to certain sense experience.
Having narrowed our focus to Propositional knowledge, we must now ask ourselves what exactly, constitutes knowledge. What does it mean for someone to know something? Epistmologists have usually undertaken this task by seeking a correct and complete analysis of the concept of knowledge, in other words, a set of individually necessary and jointly sufficient conditions which determines whether someone knows something.
TRADITIONAL EPISTEMOLOGY
The prime concern of epistemology is found in Plato’s dialogue Theateatus, where Plato exposited a definition of knowledge, by distinguishing it from ignorance and opinion.[4] That justified true belief is knowledge, is not a definition on which Plato had faith, justified by sufficient reasons. From Platonic dialogue to present day philosophical concern, still this area beg unending debate to answer this classic question. But there is a paradigm shift, explicitly diversified philosophical endeavor to find a satisfactory answer to several questions like what knowledge is, how we can know something or about justification of knowledge etc.
So a traditional epistemology stemmed from skeptic challenge in Greek age, turned to be analytic and psychoanalytic one in modern age. Philosophers from Vienna circles and analytic philosophers extended area of epistemology and methods to justify knowledge.
Traditional epistemology is defined as an epistemic enterprise concerned with the object we know, which was initiated by Plato and continued till the age of Descartes. In fact, Cartesian skepticism was a vigorous attempt to justify knowledge in traditional school.
KNOWLEDGE AS JUSTIFIED TRUE BELIEF
Having established that Propositional knowledge is of epistemological interest, we shall then refer to such knowledge using he schema; ‘S knows that p ’, where ‘S’ stands for the subject who has knowledge and ‘p’ for the proposition that is known. Our question will be: What are the necessary and sufficient conditions for S to know that p? We may distinguish, broadly, between a traditional and a non- traditional approach to answering this question. According to the traditional approach, knowledge that p is, at least approximately, justified true belief (JTB). False propositions cannot be known.[5] Therefore, knowledge requires truth. A proposition S that doesn't even believe can't be a proposition that S knows. Therefore, knowledge requires belief. Finally, S’s being correct in believing that p might merely be a matter of luck. Therefore, knowledge requires a third element, traditionally identified as justification. Thus we arrive at a tripartite analysis of knowledge as Justified True Belief (JTB): S knows that p if and only if p is true and S is justified in believing that p. According to this analysis, the three conditions — truth, belief, and justification — are individually necessary and jointly sufficient for knowledge. Initially, we may say that the role of justification is to ensure that S 's belief is not true merely because of luck. On that, the Traditional and Non Traditional approach are in agreement. They diverge, however, as soon as we proceed to be more specific about exactly how justification is to fulfill this role. According to the traditional approach, S's belief that p is true not merely because of luck when it is reasonable or rational, from S 's own point of view, to take p to be true. According to evidentialism, what makes a belief justified in this sense is the possession of evidence. The basic idea is that a belief is justified to the degree it fits S 's evidence. Non Traditional approach, on the other hand, conceives of the role of justification differently. Its job is to ensure that S's belief has a high objective probability of truth and therefore, if true, is not true merely because of luck. One prominent idea is that this is accomplished if, and only if, a belief originates in reliable cognitive processes or faculties. This view is known as reliabilism.[6]
CRITIQUE OF THE TRADITIONAL EPISTEMOLOGY
Traditional Epistemology may in many ways seems to enunciate an attractive and indeed necessary project for the pursuit of rational cognitive enquiry, even if not quite in the manner conceived of by Descartes; there are also many philosophers today who would concur in such an assessment. The view of most who would call themselves naturalists, however, is that it suffers from irredeemable problems of diverse kinds, and that a priori norms do not and cannot constitute, contrary to first impression, a necessary foundation for our substantive world-knowledge. The chief problems with Traditional Epistemology can be seen as falling into three main classes:
(a) There seems to be no viable way of justifying norms purely a priori, nor do there seem to be plausible candidates for such norms (the epistemological problems).
(b) We cannot make sense of the nature of the truths that would constitute the objects of the assumed, purely a priori apprehension, nor of the mental act that would be involved in grasping them (the metaphysical problems).
(c) It is unclear that we can even make sense of the need for epistemic norms, or motivate particular proposals about what these norms should be, without assuming a good deal of substantive scientific knowledge (the methodological problems).[7]
Of these three classes, (b) is probably the most contentious standing alone, whilst, in a broad sense of 'methodological', (c) is perhaps the most fundamental.
THE GETTIER PROBLEM
For some time, the justified true belief (JTB) account was widely agreed to capture the nature of knowledge. However, in 1963, Edmund Gettier published a short but widely influential article which has shaped much subsequent work in epistemology. Gettier had shown that the tripartite analysis of knowledge as justified true belief has been shown to be incomplete.[8] There are cases of justified true belief that do not qualify as cases of knowledge. Justified true belief, therefore, is not sufficient for knowledge. Cases like that — known as Gettier-cases — arise because neither the possession of evidence nor origination in reliable faculties is sufficient for ensuring that a belief is not true merely because of luck. Consider the well-known case of barn-facades: Henry drives through a rural area in which what appear to be barns are, with the exception of just one, mere barn facades. From the road Henry is driving on, these facades look exactly like real barns. Henry happens to be looking at the one and only real barn in the area and believes that there's a barn over there. Henry's belief is justified, according to Traditional Knowledge, because Henry's visual experience justifies his belief. According to Non Traditional Knowledge, his belief is justified because Henry's belief originates in a reliable cognitive process: vision. Yet Henry's belief is plausibly viewed as being true merely because of luck. Had Henry noticed one of the barn-facades instead, he would also have believed that there's a barn over there. There is, therefore, broad agreement among epistemologists that Henry's belief does not qualify as knowledge. To state conditions that are jointly sufficient for knowledge, what further element must be added to justified true belief? This is known as the Gettier problem.[9] According to Traditional Knowledge, solving the problem requires a fourth condition. According to some Non Traditional Knowledge theorists, it calls for refining the concept of reliability. For example, if reliability could suitably be indexed to the subject's environment, reliabilists could say that Henry's belief is not justified because in his environment, vision is not reliable when it comes to discerning barns from barn-facades. Some Non Traditional Knowledge theorists bypass the justification condition altogether. They would say that, if we conceive of knowledge as reliably produced true belief, there is no need for justification. Reliabilism, then, comes in two forms: as a theory of justification or as a theory of knowledge. As the former, it views justification to be an important ingredient of knowledge but, unlike Traditional Knowledge, grounds justification solely in reliability.[10] As a theory of knowledge, reliabilism asserts that justification is not necessary for knowledge; rather, reliably produced true belief (provided the notion of reliability is suitably refined to rule out Gettier cases) is sufficient for it.
RESPONSES TO THE GETTIER PROBLEM
Gettier's problem has attracted a range of responses. The different directions that these responses have taken are constrained by the structure of Gettier's argument: if knowledge is solely justified true belief, then there cannot be any cases of justified true belief that are not also cases of knowledge; but Gettier claims that his counterexamples are cases of justified true belief without being cases of knowledge.[11] Therefore, in this account, one is to either accept Gettier's conclusion — and elucidate a new conceptual analysis for knowledge — or else deny one of Gettier's two claims about his counterexamples (that is, either deny that Gettier cases are justified true beliefs, or else accept that Gettier cases are knowledge after all). One response, therefore, is that in none of the above cases was the belief justified: it is impossible to justify anything which is not true. Under this interpretation the JTB definition of knowledge survives. The problem is now not to define knowledge but to define justification.[12]
No-False-Belief Condition
Some people argue that knowledge involves certainty.  One way of  expressing  this  is  to claim  that  a  belief  is  not  justified unless  you  can  be certain  of  it.  ‘Certainty’  here doesn’t mean  a  psychological  feeling  (which  could vary from  one person  to  another),  but  refers to  the belief  being  certain.  We could use this  view of  justification  to  argue that  Gettier cases  demonstrate that  we cannot  be certain  of  our beliefs  in  normal  cases.  Because we can’t  tell  whether we are in  a  normal  case or a  Gettier case,  then  our beliefs  in  normal cases  are not  certain,  and so  are not  justification.[13]  Gettier doesn’t show that knowledge is not justified true belief.  What he shows is that our beliefs are rarely justified. However, it is rare that our evidence rules out the leads to skepticism possibility of error.  So  infallibilism can  object  that  a  belief  can  be justified without  being  true.  good evidence.[14] It seems pointless, though, to insist on the infallibility of belief precisely because we believe what we do because we believe that what we believe is true and we divest ourselves immediately and involuntarily of a belief when we come to believe that that belief is false.
Alvin Goldman's Theory of Knowing
The causal theory of knowing is one of the early versions of externalism, introduced by Alvin Goldman and conceived primarily as a response to the Gettier problem. It states that in order for there to be knowledge, there must be a causal chain, however complex, between the individual’s belief in some proposition, and the truth of the proposition itself. So, we might insist that to constitute knowledge, a belief must be both true and justified, and its truth and justification must be connected somehow. This notion of a connection between the truth and the justification of a belief turns out to be difficult to formulate precisely, but causal accounts of knowledge seek to capture the spirit of this proposal by more significantly altering the analysis of knowledge.[15] Such accounts maintain that in order for someone to know a proposition, there must be a causal connection between his belief in that proposition and the fact that the proposition encapsulates. This retains the truth condition, since a proposition must be true in order for it to encapsulate a fact. However, it appears to be incompatible with fallibilism, since it does not allow for the possibility that a belief be justified yet false.
Lehrer-Paxson's Defeasibility Condition
Keith Lehrer and Thomas Paxson proposed another response, by adding a defeasibility condition to the JTB analysis. On their account, knowledge is undefeated justified true belief — which is to say that a justified true belief counts as knowledge if and only if it is also the case that there is no further truth that, had the subject known it, would have defeated her present justification for the belief. (Thus, for example, Smith's justification for believing that the person who will get the job has ten coins in his pocket is his justified belief that Jones will get the job, combined with his justified belief that Jones has ten coins in his pocket. But if Smith had known the truth that Jones will not get the job that would have defeated the justification for his belief.) However, many critics (such as Marshall Swain ) have argued that the notion of a defeater fact cannot be made precise enough to rule out the Gettier cases without also ruling out a priori cases of knowledge.[16]
Fred Dretske's Conclusive Reasons
Fred Dretske is an epistemologist who proposed in his 1971 essay "Conclusive Reasons," that evidence, grounds, and reasons should be considered as justifications for beliefs. He says that we can say of any subject, S, who believes that P and who has conclusive reasons for believing that P, that, given these reasons, he could not be wrong about P or, given these reasons, it is false that he might be mistaken about P. Suppose, then, that
(1) S knows that P and he knows this on the basis (simply) of R entails
(2) R would not be the case unless P were the case.[17]
The latter formula expresses a connection between R and P which is strong enough, we can say that if (2) is true, then R is a conclusive reason for P. For if (2) is true, we are entitled, not only to deny that, given R, not-P is the case, but also that, given R, not-P might be the case. That is to say, (2) eliminates R and not-P as a possible (joint) state of affairs and, when we are given R, it eliminates not-P as a possible state of affairs. This is so because (2) entails the falsity of, (3) Although R is the case P might not be the case. But how can Dretske's claim that the evidence, grounds, or reasons must be "conclusive" strengthen the case for knowledge? He admits there are many examples of mistaken knowledge claims, one where the thermometer used is known to stick at readings above 98.6 degrees and another example of mistaken testimony.[18]
Robert Nozick' Truth-Tracking Condition
A tracking theory of knowledge is one that describes knowledge as a belief that tracks the truth in a reliable way. The tracking theory of knowledge was created by Robert Nozick as an attempt to deal with Gettier counterexamples to the previous definition of knowledge — that knowledge is justified true belief. Nozick describes four conditions for how a person, S, can have some knowledge of a proposition, P. In order for S to know P, Nozick says that these conditions must be met:
1. P is true
2. S believes that P
3. If it were not the case that P (i.e., if ¬P), S would not believe that P
4. If it were the case that P, S would believe that P[19]
Nozick's definition is known as a truth-tracking one. Knowledge is such because it tracks the truth — justification of a belief is only valid insofar as it reliably keeps track of what is true. Nozick's third and fourth conditions are counter factuals. He called this the "tracking theory" of knowledge. Nozick believed the counterfactual conditionals bring out an important aspect of our intuitive grasp of knowledge: For any given fact, the believer's method must reliably track the truth despite varying relevant conditions. In this way, Nozick's theory is similar to reliabilism.
Richard Kirkham's skepticism
Richard Kirkham has proposed that it is best to start with a definition of knowledge so strong that giving a counterexample to it is logically impossible. Whether it can be weakened without becoming subject to a counterexample should then be checked. He concludes that there will always be a counterexample to any definition of knowledge in which the believer's evidence does not logically necessitate the belief. Since in most cases the believer's evidence does not necessitate a belief, Kirkham embraces skepticism about knowledge. He notes that a belief can still be rational even if it is not an item of knowledge.[20]
However, most contemporary epistemologists accept Gettier's conclusion. Their responses to the Gettier problem, therefore, consist of trying to find alternative analyses of knowledge. They have struggled to discover and agree upon as a beginning any single notion of truth, or belief, or justifying which is wholly and obviously accepted. Truth, belief, and justifying have not yet been satisfactorily defined, so that JTB (justified true belief) may be defined satisfactorily is still problematical, on account or otherwise of Gettier's examples.
THE STRUCTURE OF JUSTIFICATION
Every belief is based on assumptions, and those assumptions are based on other assumptions, which are based on others, and so on, until we are left with assumptions that we simply accept even though we have no justification for doing so. This is known as the 'regress' argument, and there are several ways to resolve it. Firstly, we could suggest that the regress stops at unjustified beliefs. This would be epistemological nihilism - a denial of genuine justification.[21] A second option is to say that the regress stops at intrinsically justified (or 'self evident') beliefs. This is called foundationalism.  According to foundationalism, our justified beliefs are structured like a building: they are divided into a foundation and a superstructure, the latter resting upon the former. Beliefs belonging to the foundation are basic. Beliefs belonging to the superstructure are non-basic and receive justification from the justified beliefs in the foundation. The final option is to never stop the regress.[22] This is called Coherentism. According to coherentism, the foundationalism metaphor gets things wrong. Knowledge and justification are structured like a web where the strength of any given area depends on the strength of the surrounding areas. Coherentists consider the structure of justification to be circular rather than linear. Quine speaks of a mutually-reinforcing 'web of beliefs', where every belief is justified to the extent that it coheres with all the others.[23]
Contextualism refers to the position that the truth-conditions knowledge-ascribing and knowledge-denying sentences (sentences of the form “S knows that P” and “S doesn’t know that P” and related variants of such sentences) vary in certain ways according to the context in which they are uttered. In his influential paper, “A Contextualist Theory of Epistemic Justification,” David Annis presents what he calls “contextualism” as an alternative to both foundationalism and coherentism in the issue of the structure of justification.  Now, some Epistemologists think that even Annis’s “contextualism” is not a structural alternative to those two theories, but is rather best construed as a form of foundationalism.  But the vital point to be made now is that “contextualism” as construed here, is certainly not a thesis about the structure of knowledge or of justification.  It is, in fact, consistent with either foundationalism or coherentism.
CONCLUSION
In this essay we have examined the concept of epistemology - as the theory of knowledge and justified belief, which inquires into the source, limits and nature of knowledge. In his Republic Plato describes knowledge as "what is," and inerrant. Whereas in his Theaetetus, he sees knowledge as true belief that is tied down (justified). Thus we have a tripartite Theory of knowledge - justification, truth, and belief. This would, however, imply a Propositional dimension to knowledge.
Through his counterexamples, Edmund Gettier argues that there are cases of beliefs that are both true and justified—therefore satisfying all three conditions for knowledge on the JTB account—but that do not appear to be genuine cases of knowledge. Thus a fourth condition (JTB+G) is required. Gettier's point is based on justification. For not providing a solution to this problem, Gettier has made it attract a range of responses - Alvin Goldman's causal condition, and Lehrer - Paxson's defeasibility condition. Others include the revision of the JTB responses like the Fred Dretske's Conclusion Reasons, Robert Nozick's truth-tracking, and Richard Kirkham's scepticism. Moreover, before Gettier's paper, there is no structure of justification. Most epistemological discourses, however, agree on foundationalism, coherentism, and contextualism (i.e the Regress problem) making up the structure of justification.
Subsequently, while this article provides an overview of the important issues, it of course leaves the most basic questions unanswered; epistemology will continue to be an area of philosophical discourse as long as these questions remain.







REFERENCE
Audi, Robert. The Structure of Justification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 1993
Bonjour, Laurence. 1985. The Structure of Empirical Knowledge. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Bonjour Lawrence. Epistemology: Classical Problems and Contemporary Responses (2nd ed.). New York: Rowman and Little field Publishers, Inc., 2010.
Chisholm, Roderick. 1989. Theory of Knowledge. 3rd edition. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall.
Chisholm, Roderick. 1982. The Foundations of Knowing. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Dretske, Fred. 1970. “Epistemic Operators.” The Journal of Philosophy, 67: 1007–23.
Haack, Susan. Evidence and Inquiry. Towards Reconstruction in Epistemology. . Oxford: Blackwell 1993.
Huemer, Michael. Skepticism and the Veil of Perception. New York: Rowman and Littlefield, 2000.
Lehrer, Keith. 1990. Theory of Knowledge. Boulder: Westview Press.
Nozick, Robert. 1981. Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Sosa Ernest. “The Raft and the Pyramid,” in Linda Alcof (ed.), Epistemology: The Big Questions I. Massachusetts: Blackwell Publishers Ltd, 1998.

Sosa, Ernest. Knowledge in Perspective. Selected Essays in Epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991
Steup, Matthias and Sosa, Ernest (eds). Contemporary Debates in Epistemology. Malden (MA): Blackwell, 2005.
Steup, Matthias, "Epistemology", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring2014Edition),EdwardN.Zalta(ed.),URL=<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/epistemology/>.
 Truncellito David A. Epistemology. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2005.
Plato, Meno and Theaetetus, In Complete Works, J. Cooper, (ed.), Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 1997.
Williams, Michael.  Groundless Belief. Pinceton: Princeton University Press 1999a


[1] Lawrence Bonjour, Epistemology: Classical Problems and Contemporary Responses (2nd ed.), (New York: Rowman and Little field Publishers, Inc., 2010), p. 154.
[2] Keith Lender, "The Better Problem and the Analysis of Knowledge," in The Analysis of Knowledge, p. 17.
[3] David A. Truncellito, Epistemology, (Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2005).
[4]Cf. Plato, Meno and Theaetetus, In Complete Works, J. Cooper, (ed.), (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 1997), p. 186.
[5]Steup, Matthias, "Epistemology", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/epistemology/>.
[6] Steup, Matthias, "Epistemology", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/epistemology/>.
[7]Ernest Sosa,Knowledge in Perspective”, Selected Essays in Epistemology, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), p. 54.
[8] Michael Huemer, Skepticism and the Veil of Perception, (New York: Rowman and Littlefield,2000), p. 345.
[9]Susan Haack, “Evidence and Inquiry,” Towards Reconstruction in Epistemology, (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993), p. 67.
[10] Matthias Steup and Ernest Sosa, (eds), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, (Malden (MA): Blackwell Press, 2005), p. 45.
[11] Roderick Chisholm, Theory of Knowledge, 2nd ed. (Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentyice-Hall, Inc., 1997), p. 117.
[12] Lawrence Bonjour, Epistemology: Classical Problems and Contemporary Responses (2nd ed.), (New York: Rowman and Little field Publishers, Inc., 2010), p. 159.
[13]Cf. Ernest Sosa, ‘Knowledge in Perspective’, Selected Essays in Epistemology, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), p. 231.
[14] W. V Quine, “Epistemology Naturalized.” In: Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, (New York: Columbia Press, 1969), p. 70.
[15]Cf. Alvin Goldman, “Discrimination and Perceptual Knowledge,  The Journal of Philosophy1976, 73: 771–791.
[16] Keith Lehrer, Theory of Knowledge, (Boulder: Westview Press, 1990), p. 121.
[17] Cf. Fred Dretske, “Epistemic Operators.” The Journal of Philosophy, 1997, p. 21.
[18] Roderick Chisholm, The Foundations of Knowing, ( Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1982) p. 98.
[19]Robert Nozick, Philosophical Explanations, (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1981), p. 122.
[20]Cf Michael Williams, Groundless Belief, (Pinceton: Princeton University Press, 1999), p. 34.
[21] Cf. Laurence Bonjour, The Structure of Empirical Knowledge, (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1985), p. 98.
[22] Robert Audi, The Structure of Justification, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993)p. 154.
[23] Ernest Sosa, “The Raft and the Pyramid,” in Linda Alcof (ed.), Epistemology: The Big Questions I(Massachusetts: Blackwell Publishers Ltd, 1998), p. 195.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

SUMMARY OF PROVIDENTISSIMUS DEUS, ENCYCLICAL LETTER OF POPE LEO XIII ON THE STUDY OF THE HOLY SCRIPTURE.

summary and appraisal of chapters one, two and three of the book The African Origin of Greek Philosophy: An Exercise in Afrocentrism, by Innocent C. Onyewuenyi.

THE LAST THREE WAYS TO PROVES GOD'S EXISTENCE BY THOMAS AQUINAS