What is art?
What is art?
The
definition of art is quite controversial in contemporary philosophy. Whether
art can be defined is a matter of controversy, and, the philosophical
usefulness of a definition of art has also been debated. This has raised a host
of sceptical reactions about the need for defining art.
Scepticisim about definitions
Skepticism
about the possibility and value of a definition of art has been an important
part of the discussion in aesthetics since the 1950s on, and though its
influence has subsided, uneasiness about the definitional project persists.
A common
family of arguments, inspired by Wittgenstein’s famous remarks about games, has
it that the phenomena of art are, by their nature, too diverse to admit of the
unification that a satisfactory definition strives for, or that a definition of
art, were there to be such a thing, would exert a stifling influence on
artistic creativity.
A second
sort of argument, less common today than in the heyday of a certain form of
extreme Wittgensteinianism, urges that the concepts that make up the stuff of
most definitions of art (expressiveness, form) are embedded in general
philosophical theories which incorporate traditional metaphysics and
epistemology. But since traditional metaphysics and epistemology are prime
instances of language gone on conceptually confused holiday, definitions of art
share in the conceptual confusions of traditional philosophy.
A third
sort of objection rejects the project of defining art as an unwitting (and
confused) expression of a harmful ideology. On this view, the search for a
definition of art presupposes, wrongly, that the concept of the aesthetic is a
creditable one. Definitions of art, consequently, spuriously confer
ontological dignity and respectability on social phenomena that probably in
fact call more properly for rigorous social criticism and change. Their real
function is ideological, not philosophical.
A fourth
argument against defining art, with a normative tinge that is psychologistic
rather than socio-political, takes the fact that there is no philosophical
consensus about the definition of art as reason to hold that no unitary concept
of art exists. Concepts of art, like all concepts, after all, should be used
for the purpose(s) they best serve. But not all concepts of art serve all
purposes equally well. So not all art concepts should be used for the same
purposes. Art should be defined only if there is a unitary concept of art that
serves all of art’s various purposes—historical, conventional, aesthetic,
appreciative, communicative, and so on. So, since there is no
purpose-independent use of the concept of art, art should not be defined
But these
do not preclude the need for ‘guiding-specifying’ definitions anyway. According
to Thomas Adajian, in the history of philosophy, the definition of art is
divided into two: Traditional and Contemporary.
Traditional Definitions
Traditional
definitions, at least as commonly portrayed in contemporary discussions of the
definition of art, take artworks to be characterized by a single type of
property. The standard candidates are representational properties, expressive
properties, and formal properties. Thus, there are representational or mimetic
definitions, expressive definitions, and formalist definitions, which hold that
artworks are characterized by their possession of, respectively,
representational, expressive, and formal properties.
We shall
highlight two personages here: Plato and Kant
First,
Plato holds in the Republic and elsewhere that the arts are
representational, or mimetic (sometimes translated
“imitative”). Artworks are ontologically dependent on, and inferior to,
ordinary physical objects, which in turn are ontologically dependent on, and
inferior to, what is most real, the non-physical Forms. Grasped perceptually,
artworks present only an appearance of an appearance of what is really real. Consequently,
artistic experience cannot yield knowledge. Nor do the makers of artworks work
from knowledge. Because artworks engage an unstable, lower part of the soul,
art should be subservient to moral realities, which, along with truth, are more
metaphysically fundamental and hence more humanly important than beauty. Beauty
is not, for Plato, the distinctive province of the arts, and in fact his
conception of beauty is extremely wide and metaphysical: there is a Form of
Beauty, of which we can have non-perceptual knowledge, but it is more closely
related to the erotic than to the arts.
Second,
although Kant has a definition of art, he is for systematic reasons far less
concerned with it than with aesthetic judgment. Kant defines art as “a kind of
representation that is purposive in itself and, though without an end,
nevertheless promotes the cultivation of the mental powers for sociable
communication”. The definition, when fully unpacked, has representational,
formalist and expressivist elements. Located conceptually in a much broader
discussion of aesthetic judgment and teleology, the definition is one
relatively small piece of a hugely ambitious philosophical structure that
attempts, famously, to account for, and work out the relationships between,
scientific knowledge, morality, and religious faith.
Contemporary Definitions
Here,
definitions of art attempt to make sense of two different sorts of facts: art
has important historically contingent cultural features, and it also, arguably,
has trans-historical, trans-cultural characteristics that point in the
direction of a relatively stable aesthetic core. Under contemporary
definitions, we have conventionalist and functionalist definitions.
Conventionalist definitions take art’s cultural features to be explanatorily
fundamental, and attempt to capture the phenomena—revolutionary modern art, the
traditional close connection of art with the aesthetic, the possibility of
autonomous art traditions, etc.—in social/historical terms. Non-conventionalist
or “functionalist” definitions reverse this explanatory order, taking a concept
like the aesthetic (or some allied concept like the formal, or the expressive)
as basic, and aim to account for the phenomena by working that concept harder,
perhaps extending it to non-perceptual properties.
Conventionalist definitions
Conventionalist
definitions deny that art has essential connection to aesthetic properties, or
to formal properties, or to expressive properties, or to any type of property
taken by traditional definitions to be essential to art. Conventionalist
definitions come in two varieties, institutional and historical.
Institutional: Institutionalist conventionalism, or
institutionalism is a synchronic view, which typically holds that to be a work
of art is to be an artifact of a kind created, by an artist, to be presented to
an artworld public. The most prominent and influential institutionalism is that
of George Dickie. Dickie’s institutionalism has evolved over time. According to
an early version, a work of art is an artifact upon which some person(s) acting
on behalf of the art-world has conferred the status of candidate for
appreciation
Historical: Historical conventionalism is a diachronic view which holds
that artworks necessarily stand in an art-historical relation to some set of
earlier artworks. Historical definitions hold that what characterizes artworks
is standing in some specified art-historical relation to some specified earlier
artworks, and disavow any commitment to a trans-historical concept of art, or the
“artish.” Historical definitions come in several varieties, but, cccording to
the best known version, Levinson’s intentional-historical definition, an
artwork is a thing that has been seriously intended for regard in any way pre-existing
or prior artworks are or were correctly regarded.
Functional Definitions
Functional
definitions take some function(s) or intended function(s) to be definitive of
artworks. Here only aesthetic definitions, which connect art essentially with
the aesthetic—aesthetic judgments, experience, or properties—will be
considered. Monroe Beardsley for example avers that an artwork is “either an
arrangement of conditions intended to be capable of affording an experience
with marked aesthetic character or (incidentally) an arrangement belonging to a
class or type of arrangements that is typically intended to have this
capacity.”
Zangwill’s
aesthetic definition of art says that something is a work of art if and only if
someone had an insight that certain aesthetic properties would be determined by
certain nonaesthetic properties, and for this reason the thing was
intentionally endowed with the aesthetic properties in virtue of the
non-aesthetic properties as envisaged in the insight.
My Position
From the
foregoing, something is clear in Plato’s thoughts. And that is, that art
approximates the perfect, the beautiful and the good. This is true because
every art work is a product of the human agent, and the human agent is fraught
with the possibility of error. Error is undeniable with regard to human beings
insofar as human beings are spatio-temporally limited. From these thoughts too,
it is clear that the perfect, beautiful, and good are ideals which every art
work attempts to approximate, whether we perfectly attain this is not the
question of aesthetics. Aesthetics is a science of oughtness and this confers a
subtle legitimacy in Plato’s thoughts and makes me find it appealing.
Comments
Post a Comment