WHAT IS JUSTIFICATION , WHY DOES IT MATTER IN EPISTEMOLOGY, THREE THEORIES OF JUSTIFICATION.
WHAT IS JUSTIFICATION , WHY DOES IT MATTER IN EPISTEMOLOGY,
THREE THEORIES OF JUSTIFICATION.
Plato in the Thaetetus
makes a distinction between knowledge and true belief. He argues in this
dialogue that knowledge is not similar to true belief, and as such argues
against the identification of knowledge as true belief simply on the grounds
that a jury for instance may believe truly that a defendant is guilty, but not
have strong evidence to claim knowledge to this effect. Something, then, is
required for knowledge than mere true belief alone. From the Thaetetus, all that is needed for true
belief to become knowledge is the right to believe or the justification of such
a belief. It is this third condition that makes a true belief knowledge. A true
belief, then, must be justified in order to be referred to as knowledge.
Justification, then, in epistemology
is a methodic speech act in which we advance or adduce reasons either in favour
of or against any given motion. Justification could be either via positive or
via negativa; it could also be inferential if a set of premises are needed in
order to arrive at some justification or non-inferential if no premises are
needed in order to arrive at some justification. Justification could also be
prima facie which is based simply on face-value or ultima facie which is
absolutistic (which we avoid in epistemology). Justification could also be
synchronic (applicable to a certain expanse of space-time) or diachronic
(traversing many regions of space-time slices). It could also be deontological
(offered perfunctorily) or non-deontological (offered non-perfunctorily).
Why does Justification matter in Epistemology?
Justification matters a lot in epistemology because, it is imposed to
rid of accidentally true beliefs or lucky guesses. It is a source of stability
for beliefs.
Again, justification matters because it is part of the three (3) conditions
that are necessary for knowledge since epistemology is the study of knowledge,
precisely propositional knowledge which means ‘knowing that such and such.’
Knowledge without justification is incomplete. It is justification, true belief
tied down to an account, that makes true beliefs attain the status of
knowledge.
On the first condition of knowledge: Whereas knowledge entails beliefs in the sense that
if a person knows something he/she must believe it, knowledge is not the same
as belief. In Plato’s clarification, while belief is unstable and uncertain,
knowledge is stable and certain. While knowledge is based on conclusive
evidence, belief is not.
On the second condition of knowledge: Since knowledge cannot be referred to as belief, this
leads to the second condition of knowledge, that is, truth. For a belief to be
qualified as a knowledge claim, it must be true. But, belief even if it turns
out to be true is not knowledge, unless, we have the right to believe it or
that the true belief is justified (tied down to an account). This shows why
justification is matters in epistemology. It is justification that confers
epistemic status on our true beliefs. Akin knows that A if and only if 1) A is
true 2) Akin believes that A and 3) Akin is justified in believing that A.
Justification makes our true beliefs
to be explained or defined in some philosophically convincing way. It really
matters in epistemology because its absence greatly minimizes the legitimacy of
one’s epistemic claims. It is a necessary condition for knowledge. It
transforms mere true beliefs into knowledge and excludes beliefs arrived at via
lucky guesses. Although one cannot have knowledge of a belief without
justification, one can be justified in believing something which is false. But,
despite these, justification still matters as its absence, makes epistemic utterances
bereft of worth.
THEORIES OF JUSTIFICATION
Three theories of justification are:
Foundationalism:
Foundationalism is
the epistemological view which holds that there exists privileged
non-inferentially given and basic propositions whose truth and certainty can be
obtained through direct and unmediated experience, and which confer
justification upon all the other empirical non-basic propositions which are
justified for a person. This tenet of foundationalism, is called the
traditional notion of grand-totalizing narratives. These basic propositions are
self-justifying and incorrigible. They are incorrigible not solely because they
are infallible but because it is logically impossible to disprove them. From
the above, the justified basic beliefs are like the substructure upon which the
superstructure of non-basic beliefs rests and receive justification.
Two
facts become clear, namely, first, foundationalism holds that there are
justified basic beliefs. Second, foundationalism holds that all justified
non-basic beliefs depend ultimately for their justification on justified basic
beliefs.
Foundationalism
is relevant to ideal life situations. Suppose for example, taking into account
the stance of fallibilist foundationalism, someone says that a certain basket
has four (4) oranges, and is asked how one knows. One would say that two
oranges were there, and one just added another two. If asked why one is
justified that they are four, one will say that the fact that two plus two is
four, justifies one’s belief. This belief is the foundation upon which other
beliefs rests. Foundationalism is the therapy that helps to cure the clinical
condition which tries to sceptically posit the possibility of an infinite
regress of justifications.
Coherentism: Coherentism
is typically defended and defined by attacking foundationalism as a viable
alternative. Coherentism, contra
foundationalism, avers that knowledge and justification are structured like a
web where the strength of any given area depends on the strength of the
surrounding areas. Coherentists, then, deny that there are any basic beliefs
and also deny that non-doxastic experiences can be sources of epistemic
justification.
Coherentism
makes justification an interconnection between beliefs. A belief derives its
credibility from it playing a role in a larger system of beliefs. Coherentism
is not atomistic but holistic. To be justified, a belief must fit in a
justified system. The system is justified on how well it hangs together
considered as a whole. Justification brings specific evidence for or against a
specific claim. Coherentists hold that
whether a belief is justified depends on how well it fits or coheres with one’s
beliefs. Thus, the belonging of a belief
to a coherent web of mutually supporting beliefs, confers a justificatory
status on it. For this reason, coherentism is sometimes called a doxastic
theory of justification. Such a theory holds that the only things that can justify
beliefs are other beliefs, and the only things that can serve as reasons or
grounds for a belief are other beliefs.
Coherentism
is relevant to ideal life situations since, many of our beliefs seem to be
reasonable or justified in virtue of the fact that they cohere or fit with our
other beliefs. Suppose for example, a detective forms the belief that Smith
stole some missing objects on the basis of his beliefs that Smith’s
fingerprints were found at the scene, that a witness saw Smith in the area at the
time of the crime, and that the stolen object was found in Smith’s room. His
belief that Smith stole the object fits or coheres with the rest of his beliefs.
In cases as this, the fact that a belief fits or coheres with the rest of one’s
beliefs makes it reasonable and justified to hold such a belief.
Reliabilism: Reliabilism
holds, roughly, that whether a belief is epistemically justified is a function
of its being the product of a reliable belief-forming process. Reliabilism
maintains that beliefs enjoy some epistemic status, ‘justification’ or
‘aptness’, in virtue of being the product of some truth conducive source, e.g.
a reliable process. Alvin Goldman (1967), a reliabilist, argues that a belief
is justified, or counted as knowledge only “if it is produced by processes that
typically yield a sufficiently high ratio of true or false beliefs.” There has
to be an appropriate causal connection between the knowledge claim and the
appropriate belief, according to Goldman, and no claim should be made if such a
connection does not hold. Thus, for a true belief to qualify as knowledge, it
must be the product of some reliable belief-forming process. It is the
reliability of our cognitive process that obliterates epistemic guesses, sheer
lucks, and turns a true belief into knowledge. For reliabilists, some examples
of such reliable cognitive processes include sense experiential processes, as
well as cognitive processes like introspection, memory and rational intuition.
Reliabilism
is relevant to ideal life situations. Suppose for example, a coffee in your cup
tastes sweet to you. What makes this justified is not the possession of some
evidence, but the fact that the processes in which they originate, perception,
introspection, memory and rational intuition, are reliable.
In conclusion, justification is
widespread in ordinary thought, and is useful as it applies to plans,
decisions, actions, hopes, wishes, fears, policies, judgements in a court of
law and many other things. Justification is the only tool with which the
epistemologist combats the sceptic, asserting the dual possibility of knowledge
and justification of knowledge.
Comments
Post a Comment