AN APPRAISAL OF JOHN MAKIE’S MORAL NIHILISM: FEMALE GENITAL MUTILATION
Introduction
From the outset
of history, mankind has developed heterogeneity of practices which are
intricately related to complex social orders and to traditional codes of
behavior. For centuries now, many of these, especially those with deleterious
effects, were gradually void while others remained. Out of those practices one
which still survives, is the practice of female circumcision according to Hilda
Taba, with its ages and its serious health complexity.[1]
Then circumcision was seen and considered as a
thing of pride, of cultural and religious value and so on. Those who accepted
it justified their claims in the social desire to terminate or reduce sexual
arousal in women so as to stop or reduce promiscuity, pre-marital sex and
adultery. However, this has turn out to be not only a major social problem, but
also a public health concern thus attracting not only the attention of health
workers, but also that of religious leaders, families, communities and even
individuals because of the physical and
emotional effects of the practice on women, young girls, and babies.[2]
The heart of the controversy lies in finding a
balance between a society's cultural self-determination, and the protection of
individuals from the violation of their human rights. However, it also seems to
generate such concerns because of the struggle for women liberation by
feminist. The thrust of the debate seems therefore to have a social-political
undertone rather than a purely ethical concern; thus generating heated public
debates. Many people have given in their time and talent to a critical analysis
and to a cerebral appraisal of the action, since this issue has strike numerous
nerves, challenged not only the fundamental understanding of body, self,
sexuality, family, and morality but also plays upon tensions relating to
cultural difference, and the relationship between women and
"tradition". Evidently, the current controversy surrounding female
genital operations is therefore inextricably linked to other contemporary
debates that concern the nature of universal "human rights" and the
ways such rights include or exclude women. Besides all these, there is also the
question of the moral grounds for the action, the procedures and the end of the
action. Thus, a quest arises: Is it ethical to circumcise or not? Is it morally
right or wrong? Triggered by these concerns, this
paper aims at using John Markie’s moral Nihilism to appraise female genital
mutilation. And to achieve this set goal, we shall progress in two sections.
The first shall be devoted to a methodic exposition of female circumcision, the
methods and forms of female circumcision and the merits and demerits of the
action. The second part shall be devoted to expounding Mackie’s moral nihilism
and applying it in evaluating the act and from there, we shall evaluate and
conclude.
Historical Appendix
As stated by Leonard J. Kouba and Judith Muasher in the article “Female
Circumcision in Africa: An Overview” (1985), there is no definitive evidence as
to where, how and when Female circumcision began and how it was done. Alison Slack in her article: “Female
Circumcision: A Critical Appraisal” acknowledged the difficulty in dating this
practice said that: “although chronicles and statistical informations are
difficult to find, it is believed that female circumcision has been practiced
for nearly 2500 years, prior to advent of
Islam or Christianity. The cultural and geographical origins of the
practice are unknown”.
However, a general
concurrency favours the view that
circumcision in general male or female dates back to ancientness and was often
perform as a ritual a way of "purifying" (making an individual a
member of a society) individuals and society by reducing the rate of
promiscuity and sexual pleasure; since human promiscuity was seen as dirty or unclean
in some societies. Dya Eldin M. Elsayed et.al. in the article “Female Genital
Mutilation and Ethical Issues” confirmed
this point by saying that Female circumcision is grounded in the social desire
in terminating or reducing the tendency of sexual arousal in women so that they
will be much less likely to engage in pre-marital sexual relationship or adultery.
Therefore, in societies were this practice
was seen as a means of purification, cutting off the pleasure-producing parts
was the obvious way to "purify" someone. Later, it was viewed in a
religious sense as a sacrifice of "sinful" human enjoyment in this
earthly life, for the sake of holiness in the afterlife. The Jews adopted
circumcision because of this religious undertone namely: “as a religious
ritual, and continues to preserve it. But even with this, while the Jews were
busy enacting laws to promote circumcision, the Romans and the Greeks were
prohibiting it. However, this custom saw many reformations.
Between 1865 to 1870 in England and USA, a new dimension was
taken. Circumcision was seen as part of medical practice quite different from
the ancient notion. Literature has it that circumcision was imposed in an
attempt to prevent masturbation without any scientific studies to know its
efficacy and safety. Recently, many committees and associations have risen to
educate people on the dangers of circumcision starting from the ad hoc
committee of American Academy of Pediatrics (AAP), The Canadian Pediatric Society (CPS) and
many other governmental and nongovernmental organizations. Today, female
circumcision is practiced in most continents of the world including Africa and
America. Female circumcision, like male circumcision, was originally an initiation
rite in Africa which signals that a child was passing from puberty into
adulthood thus becoming a full member of the community or tribe.[3]
In fact, for others the custom and the initiation rite itself were part of
tribal psychology and this operation is still regarded, in some societies, as
the very essence of an institution which has enormous educational, social,
moral, and religious implications quite apart from the operation itself.[4]
For the present, it is impossible for a member of a tribe to imagine an
initiation without clitoridectomy. Therefore, the quashing off the surgical
element in this custom means to many societies the abolition of the whole
institution since for such societies, clitoridectomy, like Jewish circumcision,
is a mere bodily mutilation which, however, is regarded as the condition essential
condition of the whole teaching of tribal law, religion, and morality. Although
custom no longer necessarily forms the backbone of tribal law, female
circumcision remains an African custom and is still cradle in the foundations
and sociological structures of the societies where it is practiced.[5]
In
most Nigerian societies, female circumcision has been seen as part of the
culture of the people. As of the year 2000, the Efik of Creek Town, Cross River
State still practiced female circumcision very faithfully as one of the rites
of initiating people into the adulthood and those who did not pass through that
stage were abused by age grade. After the young woman has been circumcised, she
will be taken to the fatting room, cared for by the elderly women and taught
holistically; the culture of the people, how to cook the traditional dishes and
how to be a good house wife. This period often ended with a big ceremony and
this brings both pride and dignity to the young maiden and the entire family. I
had an encounter with a young lady of 22 years of age and she hail from ishan
tribe of Edo state, which she told me that she was circumcised. So, as at the
year 1996, there was such ritual still practiced in that part of the world.
Female
circumcision defined
The
World Health Organization (WHO) and UNICEF in April 1997 defined female
circumcision as all procedures (ritual) involving partial or total removal of
the external female genitalia or other injury to the female genital organs
whether for cultural or other non-therapeutic reasons. Traditional circumcisers
or specialist use a blade or razor, with or without anesthesia. The age at
which it is conducted varies. They are three major types of circumcision and
Health effects differ also according to the procedure used in doing that. Most
common effect includes: chronic pain, cysts, inability to get pregnant,
complications during childbirth and fatal bleeding.
However, this is not to say that they are no known health benefits. Most of its
opponents argue that this practice is rooted in gender inequality, attempts to
control women's sexual tendency. However, even among women, there are some
others who see it as an honor, they are proud to be circumcised. These are the
ones who initiate it and carry out the operation.
Forms
of female circumcision
The practice of female circumcision can be
classified into four basic forms that vary in degrees of severity. However as Rogaias
Abusharaf has rightly pointed out, each
form of circumcision involves a different level of physical change as.[6]
- Ritualistic
circumcision: This is the first and least severe form. Here, the clitoris is
merely nicked. This causes bleeding, but little mutilation or long term
damage.
- Sunna:
sunna is an
Arabic word which means tradition. This form is mainly done by the Muslims
and it involves the removal of the clitoral prepuce (the outer layer of
skin over the clitoris), sometimes called the "hood"; the gland
and body of the clitoris remain intact. Occasionally, the tip of the
clitoris itself is removed. Sunna has been equated with male circumcision,
because the clitoris itself is generally not damaged.
There
are two types of sunna, mild sunna and modified sunna
a. Mild
Sunna: The pricking of
the prepuce of the clitoris with a sharp instrument, such as a pin, which
leaves little or no damage.
b. Modified
Sunna: The partial or
total excision of the body of the clitoris.
- Excision
or clitoridectomy: This form is a more harsh form of the practice but the most common
form. It involves the removal of the gland of the clitoris usually the
entire clitoris and often parts of the labia minora as well.[7]
- Infibulation
or Pharaonic circumcision: This is the most severe form of the practice. Virtually all of the
external female genitalia are removed. The remaining raw edges of the
labia majora are then sewn together, leaving only a tiny opening, to allow
for the passing of urine and menstrual fluid. Dahabo
Musa, a Somali woman, in a poem described infibulation as the "three
feminine sorrows": the procedure itself, the wedding night when the
woman is cut open, then childbirth when she is cut again.[8]
- Introcision: The enlargement of the vaginal orifice by
tearing it downwards manually or with a sharp instrument.
While all five forms of female circumcision have
been reported in Africa, excision and infibulation are the most common forms.
Although infibulation is commonly known as "pharaonic circumcision,"
there is little evidence to indicate that it was practiced by Pharaonic
Egyptians and its origin remains unclear.[9]
The title is claimed to have been applied by the Sudanese when the practice of
infibulation spread from Upper Egypt into the northern Sudan area. Conversely,
in Egypt it is often termed "Sudanese" circumcision.
Merits
of female circumcision
Some of the advantages of circumcision include:
satisfying the sexual pleasure for men, preservation of virginity, ensuring
safety during intercourse and childbirth, control of pre-marital sex and
infidelity in marriage. Some have added that the
clitoris is an aggressive organ when the woman is sexually aroused because the
center of sexual desire is the clitoris. Excision is thus necessary to protect
the woman against her over-sexed nature, saving her from temptation, suspicion
and disgrace while preserving her chastity. Circumcision helps preserve virgins
because once the clitoris is mutilated, the sexual desire will decrease and the
maidens will be saved from the temptation of desiring sex and its pleasure,
thus still stay put till marriage especially in societies where virginity is an
absolute pre-requisite for marriage and where an extra marital relationship
provokes a severe penalty.
Some
men reports that they enjoy sex more with circumcised women. In some societies,
the clitoris is considered unpleasant to both sight and touch and it is a sign
of maturity when a woman’s “ugly genitalia” have been removed thus the woman
will have good mental and physical health. Infibulations help women’s genitals to be smooth, dry and without
odor. Men also seem to enjoy penetrating an infibulation, because of the smooth
appearance of an infibulated vulva; in a way, it is enhances beauty of the
surface area.[10]
Infibulation increases hygiene because after sex, there is normally some
friction which can cause lacerations and increase risk of infection, so for
women to regulate this, they often introduce substances into the vagina to
reduce lubrication. Some of such substances may not be so hygienic but with
infibulations, the vulva is smoothen and kept dry and odorless.
Demerits of female circumcision
The opponents of Female genital mutilation are of the view
that the health benefits do not justify the act since the immediate, short-term
and late complications prove so. Their claim is based on
the premise that the practitioners have no medical training; even the tools
they used are not sterilized. The use of non medical equipment increases the
pains of the women, thus violate their human right. Also, this action can leave
the victim with painful menstruation (especially
infibulation),
because the menstrual flow has been obstructed. There may be difficult and painful
urination since the urine
may collect underneath the scar and cause small stones to form. There may be
damage to the urethra and bladder, leading to infections and incontinence, pains
during sex and
infertility. Women often report reduced sexual feelings which are a
serious violation of their right to enjoy sex.[11]
Psychological complications and feelings of shame and betrayal can develop.
Many argued that it a torture and degrading, inflicting pains
on the women and as such, it is disrespect for the dignity and sacredness of
the human body in general and a dehumanization of women in particular.[12]
Other people also considered that female circumcision does not confer any
health benefits and is not even an essential part of any major religious or
tradition. Such people are of the view that the practice rather than benefit,
it has deleterious effects on health and as such should be abolished.[13]
Sami went ahead to posit that for some people, male and female circumcision two
different thing, while the male own is ritualistic with less pains, the female
own has no such history but has much pains and the pains dehumanizes hence the
practice should be stopped.
Myths of Female Circumcision
The circumciser and those that practices this rituals do
made the young lady to be circumcised to believe that if she is not circumcised
her clitoris will grow very long and sweep the ground. That during the
circumcision process if the girl to circumcised shakes her hands, cry or blinks
her eye-lids she will be declare coward, she needs to withstand all pain.
Through circumcision the young girl shed blood to the ancestors, so as to have
link and blessing from her ancestors. The first child of the uncircumcised lady
will not survive, because she has not linked herself with the ancestors.
John Mackie’s Moral Nihilism
In his book Ethics: inventing right and wrong, Mackie argued for moral
nihilism. Moral nihilism
argues that just as there is no such thing as phlogiston, there is no such
thing as moral goodness, rightness, wrongness, duty, obligation, or any other
moral notion. Mackie argues that there are no objective values; values are not
“part of the fabric of the world”. He holds that certain values would have to
be objective to exist at all. Objective
values are all moral value, be
it moral goodness, rightness and wrongness, duty, obligation, an action’s being
rotten or contemptible, and so on. Some
non-moral values on the other hand includes: aesthetic values, beauty,
various kinds of artistic merit.
In
The subjectivity of values, Mackie put to the fore four arguments in favor of
moral nihilism:
a) The
argument from relativity.
b) The
argument from queerness.
c) An
argument appealing to the notion of supervenience.
d) An
argument involving alternate explanations of the genesis of our moral beliefs.
Argument
from Queerness
Mackie
argued against the existence of phlogiston by stating that:
1. Conceptual
claim:
If phlogiston existed, it would have to be stored in all flammable bodies and
released during combustion.
2. Substantive
claim:
There isn’t anything that is stored in all flammable bodies and released during
combustion.
3. Conclusion:
Phlogiston does not exist.
Mackie’s
argument from queerness in application to moral values could be interpreted as
follows:
1. Conceptual
claim:
If moral values existed, they would have to be objectively prescriptive.
2. Substantive
claim:
Nothing in the world is objectively prescriptive.
3. Conclusion:
Moral values do not exist.
By
applying the standard from categorical syllogism, Mackie proved that there is
no such thing as moral values. This is the root of moral nihilism. Mackie
insists that a claim to “objective, intrinsic, prescriptivity” has been
incorporated in the basic, conventional, meanings of moral terms.[14]
Therefore, to say that something is objectively prescriptive is to say that it
has “to-be-doneness” built into it. This is equivalent to the claim that
recognition of an objectively prescriptive feature necessarily motivates one to
act in the way prescribed by that feature.
Mackie’s
claim reveals also that if there were objectively prescriptive values, then
they would be entities or qualities or relations of a very strange sort, utterly
different from anything else in the universe.[15]
Plato’s
Forms give a dramatic picture of what [objectively prescriptive] values would
have to be; since the Form of the Good is such that knowledge of it provides
the knower with both a direction and an overriding motive. This means that if a
thing is good, it will necessarily tell the person who knows this to pursue it
and will in fact make him to pursue it. An objective good would be sought by
anyone who was acquainted with it, not because of any contingent fact that this
person, or every person, is so constituted that he desires this end, but just
because the end has “pursuedness” somehow built into it. Similarly, if there
were objective principles of right and wrong, any wrong (possible) course of action
would have not to be “doneness” somehow built into it.[16]
Apart from this, if we were aware of objectively prescriptive values, it would
have to be by some special faculty of moral perception or intuition, utterly
different from our ordinary ways of knowing everything else. This led Mackie to
conclude that we have good reason to doubt that any objective prescriptive
features exist.
John Mackie views the sole function
of morality to be that of counteracting the limitations of men’s sympathies.[17]
Other normative theories cannot adequately serve this function, not even Act
Utilitarianism, hence they should be rejected. He arrived at this by first
ascertaining that there is no objective morality rather what we have is
subjective of values with two points namely: the variableness of our beliefs
about values and the queerness of value properties and claims that the reason
people speak of morality as having objective properties is because of the
failure to distinguish between “good” and “ought”. Having done this, Mackie
arrived at the claim that universalizing moral values should not impose any
rational constraint on choice of actions or defensible patterns of behavior. By
this, normative ethics is not an attempt to discover and formulate principles
for right or wrong, good or evil. However, it is
pertinent to note how mistaken it would be to attribute “permissivism” to
Mackie’s theory of moral nihilism because nihilism does not imply that
everything is permitted. In fact, according to nihilism, there is no such thing
as permissibility.
Application of John
Mackie’s theory in circumcision
From the foregoing, Mackie is very clear about his position
and claim that moral codes are relative and these codes are only arrived at by
consensus. Moral norms regarding conduct have always differed from time to time
and from place to place, both within and between different societies. However,
it is not just the fact that different societies disagree about moral norms
that cast suspicion on objective moral values, but that people seem to approve
of the moral norms because they practice them rather than practice them because
they approve of them. The attempt by people to judge actions to be right or
wrong is as a result of their automatic reactions to them, not because they are
a particular manifestation of a general moral principle. Hence people’s differing
judgments cannot be accounted for as being consequences of general moral
principles as applied to particular circumstances.
It is paramount explicitly the very beginning of this work
that we are not in any way supporting Mackie’s arguments for moral nihilism in
totality. However, we will use his arguments to sieve out some problems in the
various positions of the female circumcision debate. To this end, we will at a
point differ from Mackie to establish our own position. Following Mackie’s
submission, one will argue that when people talk about female circumcision as
having a moral implication, a good question to ask is: are these moral
implications universal or relative? If by principle, there is no universal
moral code, and the relative moral codes are arrived at by consensus and are
approved as a moral code because it has been practiced by such societies, then
no external body has the right to campaign against the practice of female
circumcision. From our study, we see many people (especially human right
activist), campaigning against female circumcision, positing that it is an
offence against the human right of women. Such campaign is not justifiable. It
is an imposition of moral norm on a society who did not consent to such code.
Critics evidently judge the act of circumcising women to be wrong simply
because of their reaction to it.
Following Mackie’s argument against anything like moral
goodness or rightness, his argument against moral objectivity and his criteria
for a practice to pass into a moral code, this paper argues and firmly posit
that when critics say that it is not morally right or good to circumcise women,
they are not raising a moral concern. A good question to ask is: if such
concerns are not moral, what are they? This paper views the female circumcision
debate as being more of a political rather than a moral issue since there is no
objective moral code but relative codes which are arrived at by consensus and
approved after it must have been practiced and not practice them because it has
been approved. When critics try to make circumcision a moral issue, they are
trying to make people practice a moral code because it has been approved which
is in itself to squash their cultural and moral freedom as a people.
Our major claim in this paper is therefore that
the female circumcision debate is not only a moral issue but also has within
it, an embedded socio-political interest. Different from Mackie who claimed
that there is no universal moral norm, we argue that even if we should accept
that there is no universal moral code, such claims does not translate to an
absence of a moral code. If there is therefore a moral code, we can as well fix
female circumcision to be a moral argument; at least a relative moral debate
since it has tempered with the interest of the women and cause them pain, often
against their wish; and this is why we think female circumcision has generated a lot of heated public debate.
Another point we want to raise is that: it appears that those who
spare-head this debate, either for or against, are motivated not only by the
ethical concern which we have pointed out above, but also by some social and
political interest which the topic seems to embed. This is a view which was
already evident in the work of Christine J. Walley who argued that the current
controversy surrounding female genital operations is inextricably linked to
other contemporary debates that concern the nature of universal "human
rights" and the ways such rights include, or exclude, women; the cultural
rights of minorities as immigration increases in Euro-American countries; and
ultimately, the meaning and viability of "multicultural" societies.[18]
Our claim is supported by the politics in naming the act. For some, it is
better called “ Circumcision”, others go with “Mutilation”, while others even
prefer it be tagged “Torture” yet others settle for either “clitoridec-tomies”
or “excision”, or “ infibulations” and these are just few without mentioning
the names found in the languages of its practitioners.[19]
We are not ignorant of the possibility to also argue that these names
themselves, rather than point to a political quest, is an attempt to bring to
the fore, the ethical concerns of agitators or even the possibility to argue
that to see problem with naming borne form bias. However, the reason we see it
as political is because the use of such terms has an implicit assumption that
parents and relatives deliberately intends to harm children. A feminist for
instance will see the act as a further attempt by men to continue to suppress
women.[20]
Therefore, we will see in such positions, an implicit political undertone
whereby feminist critics of the practice will mask their interest in the
ethical concern and rather than come out with their quest for the liberation of
women from the oppression of the male folk, they will rather present the debate
as a purely ethical issue. That is why they will argue from the point of view
of the practice being an infliction on the human right of victims and they also
drag the debate to the ethical realm in order to make it weighty.
If the critics of female circumcision argue that the practice can result
to complications, this paper would argue that in any surgical operations
complications may be a possible resultant. And just as we cannot stop all forms
of surgery because of the possible complications, so also, it will be
irrational to stop female circumcision on the grounds of the complications it
might result. Just as we cannot say that because of the possible complications
in an appendicitis operation we will stop operating patience of appendicitis,
so also we cannot stop female circumcision on the grounds of complications.
What we should rather advocate should be an improvement in the method and the
introduction of modern surgical equipments. Furthermore, the claim of the human
rights activist can also be debunked for just as we do not need the permission
of the child to treat them of any ailment, so also we can argue that if
circumcising them will be for their social benefits, then we have to do that.
If people argue that it inflicts pains on the child, what of the times when
pediatricians diagnose a new born baby to have a tongue-tie and will have to
sweep under the tongue and snip the frenullum so that the baby can breast-feed.
The enormous pains babies undergo and the cry that echoes from hospitals during
this process! Following the same argument of human rights, we should let them
be so as to avoid this cry and the baby will continue to have poor latching.
Another
argument we will proffer is that given the history, process, advantages and the
disadvantages of circumcision, there seem to be an enormous emotional argument
both for and against the action.[21]
But an intelligent argument should not consider the action as one of the operations in isolation of its
cultural significance but, the defense of its representation as the “essence”
of an institution which has enormous educational, social, moral, and religious
implications. The moral code of
a people is bound up with its custom and symbolizes the unification of the
whole tribal organization. For that reason, when any traditional practice such
as female circumcision has become so deeply engrained in the society and gain
acceptance by virtually everyone, either passively or actively, it can serve as
a power that helps to unite the community together and provide a source of
cultural identity especially in small rural communities. So, the eradication of
such a traditional practice can lead to disaster and confusion which might lead
to the society losing its identity, defining principle, and the overall
happiness of the greater number. However, this is not to say that we are in
support of all the four forms of circumcision. We are mainly in support of the
excision or clitoridectomy.
Recommendations
However, observing all of these, this paper is of
the view that, since this practice has been ongoing for years, and since we
have discovered that those who advocates for its abolition are raising not only
a moral but also a socio-political concern, and since a careful follow of their
arguments has revealed to us that their major problem is on the method and the
after effect of the method, this paper
argues that rather than abolish a practice which has, over time gain so much
root and has become part of a culture and identity of some communities, we
should modernize the practice by introducing modern tools in the operation so
as to reduce the health effect and the psychological trauma this may cause in
future. We also propose that experts should be trained for the purpose of this
operation and education should be given to both parent and guidance on the need
to allow their children to freely choose to undergo this noble stage of
initiation. There should be no compulsion so that, approaching with joy, they will
embrace and value the need to be circumcised.
Hospitals should be equipped with modern equipment
that will facilitate this operation with minimal pain. During and after the operation, there should
be available, anesthetics to help reduce the pains. Therefore, instead of
spending the whole time trying to abolish the action, we should be thinking
about ways to improve on the procedures, ways to reduce the pains on the side
of the women.
Conclusion
This paper was aimed at using John Mackie’s moral
nihilism to appraise female circumcision. To achieve this, the paper was
sectioned into two, with the first trying to do an expose of female
circumcision while the other part was dedicated to exposing Mackie’s moral
nihilism and applying it to female circumcision has achieved. From the
foregoing, we can say that the set goals have been achieved and this method has
helped us to have a comprehensive understanding of both Mackie’s moral nihilism
and female circumcision. From here, we went ahead to evaluate the female
circumcision debate in the light of Mackie’s moral nihilism and our findings
has led us to ascertain that the agitation against female circumcision is more
of a socio-political concern than an ethical concern. This conclusion was drawn
after a careful study of the major arguments against the act. Most of the
reasons given especially those of the feminist and human right activists are
simply evidences that the women are only interested in women libration. But as
related to Mackie’s moral nihilism, the issue cannot be said to be a moral
issues on the grounds that Moral
nihilism, as proposed by Mackie does not admit of
such things as phlogiston. This implies that there is no such thing as moral
goodness, rightness, wrongness, duty, obligation, or any other moral notion.
For Mackie, there are no objective values; values are not “part of the fabric
of the world”. Therefore, such
statements like: it is not morally right or good to circumcise a woman is not
true.
Our
research has also shown us that, since there is no objective moral value, the
attempt by external bodies to stop the action of circumcising women in some
communities is not legal. Mackie conceived only of relative moral codes. These
codes are practice that has been done by a community for a long time and has
been, by consensus, translated into moral codes. These moral codes are very
relative and can change with time. So, when people intervene in a community’s
practice which is not theirs, they are imposing their own code to that
community. Therefore, it is very illegitimate for people who are not part of a
community to advocate for the abolition of the practice female circumcision in
a community practicing it. However, members of the community should be given
proper education on the benefits of being circumcised and after such education,
they should be given the freedom to choose either to be circumcised or not. And
if such freedom has been given, such people have no right to agitate.
This paper is not ignorant of the fact that; in as
much as female circumcision offers pleasurable consequences; it also has
painful impact on those who are subjected to it. We have also brought to the
fore that these consequences emanate from the procedures of the act. This
therefore led us to offer some suggestions which could be summarized in one
word: Modernization or upgrading of the practice. By this we mean that instead
of insisting on the old method and procedures, we can introduce modern
facilities and surgical equipments, which will make the surgery, like every other
surgery, less harmful, less painful and also reduce the risk of future
complications. This position was informed by the fact that female circumcision
from our findings, has helped in reducing the amount of
teen mothers, poverty stricken families with too many mouths to feed, and help
one to focus more in life rather than meaningless and sometimes life ruining
sex. With this the amount of unhappy homes, bad environments, and over
population will be much easier to handle. In addition also, the rate of abortion
will be controlled; child trafficking which is as a result of inability to care
for the child and other sins committed against children and human beings will
reduce. If our commendations are followed, the benefits will in due time
outweigh the risks.
[1] Cf. Leonard Kouba and
Judith Muasher, female circumcision in Africa; an overview
[2] Cf. Dya Eldin M.
Elsayed
et.al.http://www.docstoc.com/docs/115563396/Female-Genital-Mutilation-and-Ethical-Issues
[3] Cf. James H. Sequiera, "Female Circumcision
and Infibulation." In The Lancet II:
(1931), pp.1054-1055.
[4]Cf. Jomo
Kenyatta, Facing Mt. Kenya.
(New York: Vintage Press, 1965), p.128.
[5] Cf. Xavier Baronnet, “Concerning
Excision," in Les Mutilations
sexuelles feminines, Le Mariagep recoce. Geneva, Switzerland:S entinelles (1980)
pp. 45-47.
[6]Cf. Rogaias Abusharaf, Female circumcision: Multicultural
Perspectives (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania press, 2007), p. 27.
[7]
Cf. Leonard J. Kouba and Judith MuasherSource: “Female Circumcision in Africa:
An Overview” in African Studies Review, Vol. 28, No. 1 (Mar., 1985), pp. 95-110
URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/524569 .Accessed: 11/01/2015 22:05
[8]
Cf. Alison T. Slack, “Female Circumcision: A Critical Appraisal” in Human Rights Quarterly, Vol. 10, No. 4
(Nov., 1988), pp. 437-486 Published by: The Johns Hopkins University Press
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/761916 .Accessed: 11/01/2015 22:15
[9] Cf. Rose Oldfield Hayes, “Female Genital Mutilation, Fertility Control,
Women's Roles, and the Patri-lineage in Moder Sudan: A Functional Analysis”, in
American Ethnologist (1975), no. 2.
p.621.
[10] Cf. Fadwa El Guindi,
“Had this been your face, would you leave it as is? Female circumcision among
the Nubians of Egypt” in Female
circumcision: Multicultural Perspectives edited by Rogaias Abusharaf (Philadelphia:
University of Pennsylvania press, 2007), p.27.
[11] Cf. Fran P. Hosken, Female Sexual Mutilations: The Facts and Proposals for Action (
Lexington, MA, Women' International Networks News, 1982), 21.
[12] Cf. Obioma Naemeka, “
African Women, Colonial discourses, and Imperialist Interventions: Female
circumcision as Impertus” in Female
circumcision and the politics of knowledge:
African Women in Imperialist Discourses edited by Obioma Naemeka (London:
Greenwood Publishing, 2005),P. 30.
[13]Cf. Sami Aldeeb
Abu-Sahlieh, “Male and Female Circumcission: the myth of the difference” in Female circumcision: Multicultural
Perspectives edited by Rogaias Abusharaf (Philadelphia: University of
Pennsylvania press, 2007), p. 47.
[14] Cf. John Mackie, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong
(England: Penguin Books Ltd, 1977), pp. 108-109.
[15] Cf. John Mackie, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, p.
111.
[16] Cf. John Mackie, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong,
p. 112.
[17] Cf. John Mackie, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, p.108.
[18] Cf. Christine J. Walley, “Searching for Voices: Feminism,
Anthropology, and the Global Debate over Female Genital Operations” in Cultural Anthropology, Vol. 12, No. 3
(Aug., 1997) Wiley on behalf of the American Anthropological AssociationStable
URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/656558 pdf, Accessed: 11/12/2015 22:45, P. 406.
[19] Cf. Obioma Naemeka,
“African Women, Colonial discourses, and Imperialist Interventions: Female
circumcision as Impertus” in Female circumcision
and the politics of knowledge:
African Women in Imperialist Discourses edited by Obioma Naemeka (London:
Greenwood Publishing, 2005), p. 34.
[20] Cf. Brid Hehir, “FGM
Crusade: With Feminists like this, who needs misogynists?” www.spiked-online.com accessed 3/1/2016.
[21] Cf. Maria Mottin-Sylla
and Joelle Palmiori, Confronting Female Genital Mutilation: the role of youth
and ICTs in changing Africa (Cape Town: Pambazuka Press, 2011), p. 5-16.
Comments
Post a Comment