analysis of motion and its species


   INTRODUCTION
            Have you ever wondered how an airplane moves in the air, how an arrow moves, what causes an athlete to run faster than other athletes? Have you ever imagined why it is possible for a bird to fly, and why humans cannot? Why is it possible for things to be in one position in one moment, and be found in another in the next? Natural things are either in motion or being in potency to move. Things in motion can be defined only in the contrary of potency and act. Motion is the basic property of natural things.[1]Thus, there exists an intrinsic relationship between nature and motion.
            In this paper, we shall attempt an analysis of motion and its species. To achieve this, we shall begin with a definition of nature and motion. We shall look at the necessary factors for motion, Afterwards, we shall look at the objections to the possibility of motion, as well as Aristotle’s responses .We shall also consider  the responses of some other philosophers. Thereafter, we shall highlight its modern application, and then conclude.
DEFINITION OF NATURE
            Nature, according to Aristotle, is an inner principle or the source and cause of being moved or being at rest per se and not per accidens.[2] This means that nature is that in which it belongs primarily and not in virtue of concomitant attributes.
            Some people conceived nature as the subject and constitutive part of natural things but this idea is false if matter is considered as the whole substance. Others consider nature as form because the actual thing does not come into being until it receives a certain form. It is the form that gives the thing identity and actuality. But since the identity of a thing comes more from its act than from its potency, nature applies more to the form than to the matter even though both are nature.
DEFINITION OF MOTION
. Aristotle posits three working definitions of motion. [3]
            First, motion is defined as the fulfilment of what exists in potency, in so far as it exists in potency.[4] Thus, it is neither the potency of a thing existing in potency, for some things are actually in potency, nor the act of a thing in act. Rather, it is the act of a thing in potency, where the word “act” designates its relation to a prior potency, and the words “of a thing in potency” designate its relation to a further act.[5]
            Second, motion is defined as “the fulfilment of the mobile in as much as it is mobile.”[6] This definition is a conclusion to the previous one. Since motion is the act of what exist in potency, in so far as it exists in potency, and we know that whatever is in potency is mobile.
            In the third instance, motion is defined as the fulfilment or transition of a thing from one point (real and imagined) to another, either from its qualitative, quantitative, substantial or spatial form. This possibility of natural things to change is grounded in the principle of nature (form, matter and privation), efficient causality and final causality. Hence, to set a thing in motion implies causing it to transit from potency to act.
            It is pertinent to note that that which has the power of causing motion can only act in reference to the thing capable of being changed, and that which is capable of being changed can only suffer change under the action of that which has the power to change it. Hence, motion cannot exist apart from what moves, for there is no such thing as motion in abstract. Again, motion is action in the mover and passion in the moved. The mover (action) is also moved, this is because the mover sets the subject (passion) into motion by contact.[7]
NECESSARY FACTORS FOR MOTION
             For motion to be possible, certain factors ought to be responsible. Aristotle posits five factors responsible for motion. These include:
1.      That which directly causes motion. This we term efficient cause or the mover.
2.      That which is in motion (the mobile or subject of the motion)
3.      That in which motion takes place, namely time.
4.      A starting point or terminal of the motion.
5.      That to which motion proceeds (the end point or terminal of the motion), since every motion proceeds from something to something.
SPECIES OF MOTION
 Aristotle identified three species of motion; namely:
1.      Qualitative motion
2.      Quantitative motion
3.      Local motion (motion in respect of place or locomotion).[8]
            Motion is defined in terms of terminals, and these terminals are distinguished according to generas of the predicaments or categories. The species of motion must fall within these ten categories. The categories are: substance, quantity, quality, relation, place, time, position, state, action and passion.[9] Among these ten categories, only three admit of motion. These are: quantity, quality and place (location).[10]
Continuity and contrary extremes of possible motion can only be found in categories such as: sensible qualities, quantities and place. Thus, there are three species of motion: qualitative motion, quantitative motion and locomotion.
Qualitative Motion: Motion in respect of quality is called alteration (a general designation that is used to include both contraries). It could also be said to be motion in respect of sensible qualities. A vivid example is a change from white to black.
Quantitative Motion: This has to do with growth or decrease. There is a minimum quantity at which (the motion) of growing begins, and a maximum at which it is terminated. Motion in respect of quantity is called increase or decrease according as one or the other is designated; that is to say, motion in the direction of complete magnitude is increase while motion in the contrary direction is decrease.
Motion in respect of place (Locomotion): This may be designated by the general name of locomotion. In other words, it is called local motion. It indicates change of place or location.[11]
OBJECTIONS TO THE POSSIBILITY OF MOTION
 For want of space and time, we shall consider only two of such objections as proposed by Parmenides and Zeno.
            1. Parmenides objection to motion. Parmenides was among the first set of philosophers who objected to the possibility of change and motion. For him, change is nothing but the confusion of appearance with reality. He saw change as a mere illusion.[12]
This is Parmenides’ objection: “what is, cannot come to be (since already it is); while nothing can come to be from what is not.” [13]
The idea of this argument seems to be this: it is a case of coming to be, the resulting object is clearly a being, something that is. From what initial object does it come to be? If the initial object is what is and the resultant object is also what is, we do not really have a case of coming to be. There is no change or motion. And if the initial object is what is not, we have another kind of impossibility for nothing can come to be from what is not.
            Aristotle rejected Parmenides’ dilemma that something comes to be from what is, or from what is not.[14] He does so systematically by drawing a distinction between the two senses of “coming to be.” Is the initial object a being or a non-being? Parmenides asks. Aristotle answer is: in a way it is a being, and in a way it is not a being. And in a way it is not a being, and in a way it is not a non-being. The initial object might be an unmusical man. This, in one way is a being and in another way a non-being. The initial object is something (for it is a man) and something that is not (for it is not musical). Aristotle agrees with Parmenides that nothing comes to be out of cheer nothingness but he also maintains that, in a sense, things can come to be in a way. For instance, coincidentally, from what is not. For something can come to be from the privation, which in itself is not, and does belong to the thing.
            Note here that, the ‘music-ness’ comes to be from the compound unmusical man. What he comes to be from is in one way a non-being, since he comes to be from a privation, the ‘unmusic-ness’ or unmusical. But in a way, what he comes to be from is a being as well, for the initial object (man) is something that exists. Thus, Parmenides offers us a false dilemma that the initial object is either being or not being, but since, as we have shown, the initial object is a compound, in a way it is both.

2. Zeno’s objection to the possibility of motion
Zeno was a student of Parmenides. In a bid to defend the position of his master, Parmenides, that motion and change do not occur, he proposed his four paradoxes. 
The first is the dichotomy paradox. It states that to get to any point, we must first travel halfway, and to get to that halfway point, we must travel half of that halfway, and to get to that half of the halfway, we must first travel a half of the half of that halfway and so on infinitely, so that, for any given distance there is always a smaller distance to be covered first. and so, we can never start moving at all. Aristotle answered that, time can be divided just as infinitely as space, so that it would have infinitely little time to cover the infinitely little space needed to get started, therefore there is the possibility of motion.
The second paradox is known as the Achilles paradox. It states that, supposing Achilles is racing a tortoise, and gives the tortoise a head start. Then by the time Achilles reaches the point the tortoise started from, the tortoise will have advanced a certain distance, and by the point Achilles covers that certain distance, the tortoise will have advanced a bit farther, and so on, so that it seems Achilles will never be able to catch up with, let alone pass, the tortoise. Thus, motion is not taking place.
Aristotle responded that the paradox assumes the existence of an actual infinity of parts between Achilles and the tortoise. If there were an actual infinity –that is, if Achilles has had to take account of all the infinite points, he passed in catching up with the tortoise – it would indeed take infinite account of time for Achilles to pass the tortoise. However, there is only a potential infinite, of course, between Achilles and the tortoise, meaning that Achilles can cover the infinitely many points between him and the tortoise in a finite amount of time so long as he does not take another account of each point along the way.
The third paradox is called the Arrow paradox. It states that, an arrow at flight is really at rest. For every point in the flight, the arrow must occupy a length of space exactly equal to its own. After all, it cannot occupy a greater length, nor a lesser one. But the arrow cannot move within this length it occupies. It would need exactly the same space in which to move and it of course has none. So at every point in its flight, the arrow is at rest. And if it is at rest at every moment in its flight, then it follows that it is at rest during the entire flight.
Aristotle answered that it does not follow that the arrow does not move at all. The concept of motion can simply be understood as occupying different parts of space at different points in time.[15]   
The fourth paradox is called the stadium paradox. Zeno considered bodies of equal length aligned along three parallel racetracks within a stadium. One track contains A bodies (three A bodies are shown below); another contains B bodies; and a third contains C bodies. Each body is the same distance from its neighbors along its track. The A bodies are stationary, but the Bs are moving to the right, and the Cs are moving with the same speed to the left. Here are two snapshots of the situation, before and after.
Diagram of Zeno's Moving Rows
Zeno points out that, in the time between the before-snapshot and the after-snapshot, the leftmost C passes two Bs but only one A, contradicting the common sense assumption that the C should take longer to pass two Bs than one A. Zeno mistakenly supposes that a moving body passes both moving and stationary objects with equal speed.
Aristotle argues that how long it takes to pass a body depends on the speed of the body; for example, if the body is coming towards you, then you can pass it in less time than if it is stationary.[16]
RESPONSES FROM OTHER PHILOSOPHERS
  Thomas Aquinas, commenting on Aristotle's objection, wrote "instants are not parts of time, for time is not made up of instants any more than a magnitude is made of points. Hence it does not follow that a thing is not in motion in a given time, just because it is not in motion in any instant of that time.[17]
Moreover, before 212 BC, Archimedes had developed a method to derive a finite answer for the sum of infinitely many terms that get progressively smaller. He seems to agree with Zeno that the amount of time taken at each step is geometrically decreasing.[18]Thirdly, Nick Huggett argues that Zeno is begging the question when he says that objects that occupy the same space as they do at rest must be at rest.[19]
Fourthly, Bertrand Russell offered what is known as the "at-at theory of motion". It agrees that there can be no motion "during" a durationless instant, and contends that all that is required for motion is that the arrow be at one point at one time, at another point another time, and at appropriate points between those two points for intervening times. In this view motion is a function of position with respect to time.[20]
Contemporary Usage and Relevance
Concerning the modern usage of these arguments, more could be said in the fields of mathematics and physics. One major breakthrough in our contemporary times in the field of quantum mechanics is the “Quantum Zeno Effect,” which was proposed by two physicists Sudarshan and B. Misra in 1977. Studying quantum mechanics, they discovered that motion of a quantum system could be hindered through observation of the system.
“The Quantum Zeno Effect refers to a slowing down of the evolution of a quantum state in the limit that the state is observed continuously.”  It is a phenomenon in quantum physics where observing a particle prevents it from decaying as it would in the absence of the observation.  This discovery in quantum mechanics is based on Zeno’s arrow paradox.  It has led to the construction of the Quantum computer. Quantum computer is a computer design which uses the principles of quantum physics to increase the computational power beyond what is attainable by a traditional computer. 

Evaluation and Conclusion. To deny change is to deny motion, to deny motion is to deny the science of nature and all its constituents.
In this paper, we have attempted to understand the meanings of nature and motion. We critically analyzed the meaning of nature and motion, the three species of motion. This paper was aimed at an examination of Parmenides’ and Zeno’s objections to the possibility of motion and Aristotle’s responses to these objections.            





[1] Cf. Aristotle, Physics, Book III, part 1.
[2] Cf. Ibid.
[3] Cf. Ibid.
[4] Cf. Aristotle, Physics, loc. cit.
[5] Cf. Fr. Kenny’s note on Philosophy of Nature, p. 28.
[6]Ibid.,p. 29.                                                
[7] Cf. Aristotle, Physics, Bk III, part 2.
[8] Cf. Aristotle, Physics, Bk III, part 1.
[9]Cf.Omoregbe J., A Simplified History of Western Philosophy (Lagos: Joja Press Ltd.), p. 50.
[10] Cf. St. Thomas, op. cit., p. 34.
[11] Cf. Aristotle, Physics, loc. cit.
[12] Samuel stumpf, philosophy, history and problem, Mc Graw-Hill Inc pg. 16-18.
[13] Aristotle, physics, Book I, 190, n 21-25
[14] Aristotle, Physics, Book 1, 191 a 30.
[15] Aristotle, Physics Book vi, 239 n 33-240 n5.
[16] Aristotle, Physics, Book.vi, 240.
[17]Aquinas. Commentary on Aristotle's Physics, Book 6.861.
[18]George B. Thomas, Calculus and Analytic Geometry, Addison Wesley, 1951.
Boyer, Carl (1959).The History of the Calculus and Its Conceptual Development.Dover Publications.p. 295.ISBN 978-0-486-60509-8.Retrieved 2010-02-26. "If the paradoxes are thus stated in the precise mathematical terminology of continuous variables (...) the seeming contradictions resolve themselves."
[20]Huggett, Nick (1999). Space From Zeno to Einstein. ISBN 0-262-08271-3.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

SUMMARY OF PROVIDENTISSIMUS DEUS, ENCYCLICAL LETTER OF POPE LEO XIII ON THE STUDY OF THE HOLY SCRIPTURE.

summary and appraisal of chapters one, two and three of the book The African Origin of Greek Philosophy: An Exercise in Afrocentrism, by Innocent C. Onyewuenyi.

THE LAST THREE WAYS TO PROVES GOD'S EXISTENCE BY THOMAS AQUINAS