AQUINAS ELABORATION OF VIRTUE
INTRODUTION
Thomas
Aquinas in the ‘Disputed Questions on the Virtues’ sought out to encapsulate
the whole idea of virtue. Aquinas answered the questions in thirteen articles
of the first question on Disputed Questions on the Virtues. Nevertheless, the
objective of this work is to expose Aquinas answer on article eight where it is
asked ‘Are the virtues in us by nature?
In
order to make a proper exposition, we shall take a perfunctory look on the
articles that led to the development of the eighth article.
AQUINAS ELABORATION OF
VIRTUE
Aquinas
in elaborating the notion of virtue earnestly posited that virtue is a habit
for rational being which specify the completion of a power. Virtues are abiding
form in the subject that is good and also makes the subject good.[1]
Furthermore, Aquinas takes Augustine’s definition of virtue into assessment.
Augustine defined virtue as a good quality of mind whereby we live rightly,
which no one misuses and that God works in us without. Aquinas upholds this
definition by Augustine is adequate. He strengthens his agreement with
Augustine by building on his answer to the first article and further
identifying three criteria necessary for virtue to make a subject good which
are the subject itself, the perfection of the intellect and the mode of inherence.
These criteria are suitable for moral and intellectual virtues but not
theological virtues.[2]
Going
further in the elaboration of virtue, Aquinas determined that the power of the
soul can be a subject of virtue in certain respect. He arrived at this
determination by pointing out how subject relates to accident in three ways.
The first way is by providing its sustaining power, the second way as
relationship of potency to act and the last way by relationship of cause and
effect. Aquinas posits that given the second and third relations of subjects
and accidents, the power of the soul can be a subject of virtue.[3]
Moreover, he also illustrates how the irascible and concupiscible appetite can
be the subject of virtue. He achieved this by positing of human acts which are
certain actions that proceed from the good and which man has dominion over
them. Reason governs such human actions as it relates to sense appetite whose
good operation requires a disposition which is virtue.[4]
Aquinas
further determined that the will is not a subject of virtue since the will by
its very nature tends to the good therefore it needs no disposition to tend
towards end proper to it. Nevertheless, he acknowledges that some goods exceed
the proportion of the human will. A good like the divine goods exceeds the
human will and thus the will needs the virtue of charity and hope to tend
towards it. Also, in seeking someone else good, the will needs the virtue of
justice to tend towards it.[5]
Moreover, Aquinas also ascertained that practical
reason has the virtue of prudence as its subject. He arrived at this idea by
examining the numerous natural appetites to which humans are inclined and the
insufficiency of natural judgment to determine a particular good from the
various goods. Therefore, the practical reason is perfected by a habit in order
that it might rightly judge the human good with respect to all the things that
must be done.[6]
Having determined that, Aquinas went further to posit that faith is the virtue
that perfects the speculative intellect insofar it is commanded by the will.
ARE VIRTUES IN US BY
NATURE?
The
objections which were presented purport to the fact virtues are natural to man.
It makes this assertion from reason that the law commands the act of virtue but
men who have not the law naturally do what is of the law. Therefore, men
naturally perform virtuous acts and thus have virtue by nature. Also, nothing
more is needed in doing virtuous work other than being capable of the good.
However, Augustine says that to be capable of the good is in man naturally
since the will has dominion over his acts.
Aquinas
in responding to the question above invokes Aristotle’s idea that forms
pre-exist potentially in matter and are brought to act by an external agent. In
this light, he progresses to maintain that virtues are in us as an aptitude
from nature but their perfection is not in us from nature. By this above
assertion, Aquinas upholds the invaluable contribution of the agent in study
and exercise of virtue in order to bring it to perfection. However, there are
two ways of aptitude for perfection; the first ways is according to passive
potency while the second way is according to both active and passive potency.
The aptitude for perfection found in man is suitable in the second way because
of the nature of the specie which is common to all men and partly due to the
nature of the individual inasmuch as some are more apt than others in virtue.
Aquinas
buttresses his point by reckoning to the three ways in which man can be a subject
of virtue namely intellect, will and the lower appetites which is divided into
concupiscible and irascible. More so, Aquinas outlines the active and passive
potency in the intellect whereby the agent intellect actualizes the possible
intellect. This also he applies to the will whose inclination is an active
natural principle to every disposition acquired by the affective part through
exercise. The affective part being made visible in the irascible and the
concupiscible naturally heed to the dictates of reason and thus have a natural
receptivity to virtue which is brought to perfection in them insofar they are
disposed to follow the good of reason.
Therefore,
the beginning of virtue follows on the nature of human species which is common
to all. Nevertheless, there is another beginning of virtue which designates to
particular individual inclination to the act of a given virtue. This
inclination is not the perfection of virtue thus it needs the governance of
reason to direct the irascible and the concupiscible appetite. Hence, reason
works for the perfection of every virtue and although it is an operative
principle just like nature, it differs from it because reason relates to
opposites while nature is ordered to one.[7]
CONCLUSION
In
conclusion, Aquinas systematic development of the concept of virtue has finally
led us to the target of this work whereby Aquinas ascertained that virtues are
in us as an aptitude from nature but their perfection is achieved through the
exercise of the governance of reason to direct the irascible and the
concupiscible appetites.
[1] Thomas Aquinas, Quaestiones
Disputattae De Virtutibus, translated by Raph Mclnerny (St. Augustine’s
Press, South Bend, Indiana, 1999) Q. 1, A. 1
[2] Thomas Aquinas, Quaestiones
Disputattae De Virtutibus, translated by Raph Mclnerny (St. Augustine’s
Press, South Bend, Indiana, 1999) Q.
1, A. 2
[3] Thomas Aquinas, Quaestiones
Disputattae De Virtutibus, translated by Raph Mclnerny (St. Augustine’s
Press, South Bend, Indiana, 1999) Q.
1, A. 3
[4] Thomas Aquinas, Quaestiones Disputattae
De Virtutibus, translated by Raph Mclnerny (St. Augustine’s Press, South
Bend, Indiana, 1999) Q. 1, A. 4
[5] Thomas Aquinas, Quaestiones
Disputattae De Virtutibus, translated by Raph Mclnerny (St. Augustine’s
Press, South Bend, Indiana, 1999) Q. 1, A. 5
[6] Thomas Aquinas, Quaestiones
Disputattae De Virtutibus, translated by Raph Mclnerny (St. Augustine’s
Press, South Bend, Indiana, 1999) Q. 1, A. 6
[7] Thomas Aquinas, Quaestiones
Disputattae De Virtutibus, translated by Raph Mclnerny (St. Augustine’s
Press, South Bend, Indiana, 1999) Q. 1, A. 8
Comments
Post a Comment