Discourse on Method cogito ego sum.


Introduction
            Civilisations, empires, kingdoms, cultures, both great and small, across times and places, have come and gone; impeccable systems and ideologies have  arisen and have  shook the world, though obsolete today; great thoughts have been developed and propagated, yet with little or no effects in our world today. The ancient and medieval way of philosophising, though beautiful at their respective time, soon became ineffectual. Why is that the case? History has it that one thing common to the changes highlighted above is the quest for newness, for creativity, for meeting up to the demands of the time, a burning yearning for constructing a thought process and method that adequately relate to the prevailing challenges. The 17th century French philosopher, in the face of the challenges facing the intellectual and philosophical world of his time, and in a bid to propose a process, a method that will usher in ingenuity, growth, creativity, came to the rescue. How? He came to the rescue by developing what is today called the Cartesian method, whuch he explicated in his work “The Discourse on Method”. It is thos work of Descartes that this paper sets out to expose.
            The problematic of this paper vis-à-vis the Discourse on Method is no different from that which all quests for change, modernity, aim at. The problematic of modernity revolves around enhancement, subjectivity and autonomy. Enhancement is about moving from the old, the obsolete to the new, to the more result-oriented. This movement has the person, the subject as the emphasis. The subject is however enhanced to be capable of making laws for himself. 
The plan of this paper shall be as follows: refreshing and updating our minds on the subject modernity, a presentation of the figure of Rene Descartes, the Cartesian rationalism, the cogito ego sum. The Cartesian method versus the Socratic method, a synthesis of the six parts of discourse on the method, a panel to show its contemporary relevance today in our society, and finally conclusion.
Refreshing and update
            The old is good but the new is better. The old is good because it is the precursor of the new, the ancestor of the new, but we are aware that the new signifies progress, growth, development. It was Heraclitus, the quintessential pre-Socratic philosopher, who maintained that change is the only thing that is constant in life.[1] He maintained that one cannot step into the same water twice. But what is so special about the new? Common sense tells us that we all seek newness, creativity, ingenuity, the prominence of the subject, the emphasis on freedom, efficiency, effectiveness, modernity. Modernity, from the Latin “modernus” means “of today” “of what is current”: put differently, it refers to new method, new approach. What is more? The old is usually shrouded in myth, fear, dogmatism and fideism, immaturity and ineptitude. The new (modernity) steps in to usher in maturity, enhancement, subjectivity and autonomy. Enhancement pertains to moving from the old and often futile ways of thinking and acting to newer and more result-oriented ways. The whole enterprise of modernity is not a once in a life time expenditure, rather it is a continuous one, one that takes place every time the old becomes obsolete, and this seems to be every passing moment.
`           Prior to the 17th century AD, philosophy was caught up in the web of dogmatism and fideism, in the medieval period, and in the shackles of myths and fear, in the ancient period, But from the 17th century AD, with the arrival of Rene Descartes and Immanuel Kant into the arena of philosophical cum intellectual adventure, philosophy was to yearn for a newer and better way of philosophizing, of intellectualizing. It was only enough that philosophy had been napping and snoring in the deep sleep of feverish rationalizing, she was soon to be woken up from her dogmatic slumber  Rene Descartes came into the scene with his very popular methodic geared, geared towards promoting rationalism over and above empiricism. Descartes emphasized the subject in need of enhancement. This effort of Descartes revolutionised the whole business of philosophy. Immanuel Kant, the great German philosopher, one who was woken up from his dogmatic slumber by the skepticism of David Hume[2], also came into the theatre of philosophical enquiry with a great emphasis on a synthesis of reason/intuition with the senses. He emphasized a philosophy that is transcendental, that is reflective, that looks inward. Today, the world, and in particular philosophy, is still basking in the euphoria of modernity. Descartes and Kant have removed the scale of mediocrity and minimalism from the eyes of all humanity. But this is not the end, the enhancement continues. The future looks brighter and pregnant with better prospects of growth, of the promotion of subject, of the increase in the capacity of the subjects to make laws for themselves.
Rene Descartes
The figure of our expose is the French philosopher, Rene Descartes (1596-1650). Descartes is described as “the originator of modern philosophy, or at least the first important philosopher of our times”[3]. He is the most widely studied among all the great philosophers.[4] As a little boy growing up in Tourain, his father, Joachim Descartes referred to him as a “Little Philosopher” due to his extraordinary curiosity. Descartes is a mathematician, Physicist and a philosopher. Some historians of philosophy describe him together with Immanuel Kant as the two philosophical giants of modern period.[5]
From 1604-1612, Descartes was educated by the Jesuits in La Fleche College, a prestigious school patronised by Henry IV. The Jesuits are the members of a Religious Congregation in the Catholic Church known for the promotion of education. They are known as people of great intellectuals. La Fleche College can be compared with modern day Loyola College Abuja, a leading school in Nigeria run by the Jesuits. In La Fleche College, Descartes studied Aristotelian-Scholastic philosophy. His education included mathematics, logic, history, rhetoric and theology. During these years of his academic career, he was delighted with the certainty and precision of mathematics, compared with philosophy whose teachings always triggered doubts and disputes.[6] The early correspondences written by Descartes showed that he appreciated the value of the complete course on philosophy which he was taught by the Jesuits in the college. He described the school as one of the best schools in Europe.[7]  However, Descartes was not satisfied with the education he received at the College. He was primarily concerned with the problem of intellectual certainty. He began to reject the traditional form of knowledge which he received as a schoolboy. He held that philosophy even though it has been studied for many centuries by the most outstanding minds has not produced anything which is not in dispute and consequently doubtful.[8] He appreciated classical literature because it contained elements that stimulated the mind but he rejected it since it was incapable of guiding his behaviour. He honoured theology but concluded that its revealed truths are above the intelligence of man and could only be attained with the aid of divine assistance. Descartes was careful not to deny this truth for he remained a pious Catholic till death, but he did not find in theology the method by which its truth could be attained solely with the power of reason.[9]
At the age of twenty-two, Descartes after studying law at the University of Poitiers began to travel extensively in Europe with the hope to seek knowledge. His desire for certainty of knowledge led him to turn from his books to the book of nature. He sought no knowledge other than that which could be found only in himself or in the great book of the world. In this period, Descartes became friend with the Dutch scientist, Isaac Beekman who stimulated his interest in mathematics and science. Under the influence of Beekman, he achieved successes in science and mathematics. He invented the sine law of refraction in physics, the calculation of the angles of the bows of the rainbow in meteorology and found solution to Pappus’ problem in Geometry.[10] Descartes scientific and philosophical works were written in Holland where he lived for many years. He conceived his scientific system as a successor and better replacement of Aristotelian-scholastic synthesis which dominated European thought for centuries.[11] Scholastic philosophy shaped the intellectual climate in which Descartes grew up. In order to have a better grasp of his approach towards scholastic philosophy, it is important to note that the method of teaching in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries was influenced by scholastic thought. In this period, there were allegiance to Thomist views on theology and broad assumption of the correctness of Aristotle’s doctrines in the area of logic, natural philosophy, ethics and metaphysics.[12]
Hence, Descartes broke away from Aristotelian philosophy and gave philosophy a new start. He began to reject as force his previously acquired knowledge. All the things he used to accept as true knowledge he began to regard them as mere illusions. Since he was seeking a system of truth that would be derived from his own rational power, he ceased to rely on Aristotle and on the authority of the Church for the certainty of truth. He gave philosophy a fresh start by using only those truths he could attain through his rational powers as the foundation for all other knowledge.[13] Thus, he was the first philosopher to build a philosophy that is founded on reason.
Descartes published his main work, The Meditation on First Philosophy in 1641 with six sets of objections and his replies to them. The first sample of his work which was prefaced by the Discourse on the Method was published anonymously in 1637. In 1644, he published the Principles of Philosophy which was dedicated to Princess Elizabeth of Bohemia. His last work was The Passions of the Soul and was influenced by his discussions with Princess Elizabeth on the relation of the mind to body and the control of passion. Descartes died of pneumonia on February 11, 1650.[14] His achievements in the realm of philosophy, mathematics and science cannot be overemphasized. He is still and rightly called the father of modern philosophy in the sense that without his philosophy, the very shape of the problems which we wrestle today about knowledge and science, subjectivity and reality, matter and consciousness, would have been entirely different.[15]
Cartesian Rationalism
Rationalism- from its Latin derivative rationalis, "rational" comes from ratio, meaning ‘reason’. Consequently, rationalism is a philosophical school of thought which emphasizes reason as the primary source of knowledge, prior or superior to, and independent of sense perceptions. [16] Rene Descartes is often called the father of modern philosophy and this owing to the effect which his rationalism scheme initiated in philosophy. He is noted to have been chiefly concerned with  the problem of “intellectual certainty,”[17]  as such, it is no doubt he is a rationalist, since he in a way has been able to apply the principles of innate reasoning  by the rationalist’s method of trying to attain and prove the power of the intellect to reach truth. He emphasized reason as the basis of epistemological conquest- the knowledge of reality- more than empiricism, where knowledge is claimed to come through sense experience. Descartes demonstrated the limitations of the senses using the changes that occur in wax when it is melted. Our minds are able to grasp the true nature of substances despite changes in shape, size, colour, smell and so on. Thus, he explains that beyond acquired ideas from external things through the senses, humans are imbued with innate ideas which give us knowledge about certain realities. Descartes loved mathematical precision, certitude and indubitability. This reflected in his philosophising, so much so, that his philosophical enterprise could be described as driven by a quest to produce a system of “speculative completeness” which has a semblance of mathematical exactness.[18]  Thus, Descartes' method which tries to harness the powers of the mind with a special set of rules followed mathematical method. He insisted upon a systematic and orderly thinking through this new method.[19]
The First Rule was never to accept anything as true unless I recognized it to be certainly evidently such: that is, carefully to avoid all precipitation and prejudgment; and to include nothing in my conclusions unless it presented itself so clearly and distinctly to my mind that there was no reason for occasion to doubt it. The Second Rule was to divide each of the difficulties which I encountered into as many parts as possible, and as might be required for an easier solution. The Third Rule was to think in an orderly fashion when concerned with the search for truth beginning with the things which were simplest and easiest to understand, and gradually and by degrees reaching toward more complex knowledge, even treating as though ordered materials which were not necessarily so. The Fourth Rule was both in the process of searching and in reviewing when in difficulty always to make enumerations so complete, and reviews so general, that I would be certain that nothing was omitted.[20]

Humans, Descartes argued, are raised to the realm of knowledge through the natural powers of the mind, namely; intuition and deduction which must be orderly regulated. Intuition, for Descartes, means an intellectual activity or vision of clarity that leaves no doubt in the mind. Speaking of deduction, he rejects the Aristotelian syllogism in which conclusion follows not necessarily from facts but its premises. Descartes rather describes deduction as all necessary influence from facts that are known with certainty
Interestingly, Descartes proceeded to put everything he ever knew or believed to doubt, both physical and metaphysical including mathematics that was so certain for him. His intention was to re-construct philosophy on a firm foundation through a method of systemic or methodic doubt. Descartes' methodic doubt is a form of scepticism sometimes called provisional or methodological scepticism, and consists in doubting everything until the point is reached where nothing can be doubted. He believed that through scepticism one can rise to find knowledge that is absolute, clear, necessary and self-evident, which in turn serves as the basis for all other knowledge and the knowledge of reality.[21] Building his scepticism against all sensible things and by attributing a form of probable deception to an “evil genius,” he adopted intuition and deduction as the only rational and reliable procedure to attain knowledge.
Cogito, Ergo Sum
            The cogito ergo sum, “I think, therefore I exist” is at the heart of Rene Descartes philosophy in the Cartesian method. As mentioned above, Descartes sought out to doubt everything he had ever known. But why did he had to doubt? He felt and rightly observed that there could be deception of the senses, deception by a demon and of course deception that comes about from a state of dream. In this setting, true and certain knowledge was impossible, thus, he was led to a form of scepticism. But it dawned on him that while he was doubting everything, he was also thinking. He further observed that doubting is a function of thought, of the thinking faculty. But he wondered how one can think if one does not first exist. He therefore came to the conclusion that, doubt concerning his own existence was impossible because he needed to exist before he could even think and he needed to have the ability to think before he could doubt, consequently, that he thinks shows that he exists. Thus the only absolute certainty he was sure of, and on which he built his philosophy, was the cogito ergo sum, “I think, therefore, I am.” Every time Descartes asserts, ‘I am thinking,’ he must assert the “I” thus asserting the existence of the self who in doing the thinking.[22] Furthermore, the cogito became instrumental to prove his existence, that of other material things, and that of God. Descartes considered the cogito to be a “purely intellectual” truth, that is, one which is entirely conceptual, and a priori.[23]
The method of Descartes compared to that of Socrates
Descartes considered mathematics even though he had earlier doubted it, as a tool for effectively achieving the certainty for which human thinkers yearn. He thus proposed that we turn to mathematical reasoning as a model for achieving progress in human knowledge.[24] Furthermore, he proposed that in order to be absolutely sure that we accept only what is agenuinely certain, we must first deliberately renounce all of the firmly held but questionable beliefs we have previously acquired by experience and education.
The method of Descartes, which is mathematical in nature, can be summarised as follows:[25]
1.      Accept as true only what is indubitable.
2.      Divide every question into manageable parts.
3.      Begin with the simplest issues and ascend to the more complex.
4.      Review frequently enough to retain the whole argument at once.
Socrates
Socrates, one of the ancient philosophers, was born around 469 B.C. near Athens. His father, Sophroniscus was a sculptor and his mother Phenarate a midwife.He began a new period of history of ancient philosophy. This period is considered the qualitative leap from a cosmological to an ethical humanistic conception.[26]
Socrates versus Descartes
The Socratic Method uses questions to examine the values, principles, and beliefs of students.[27] Through questioning, the participants strive first to identify and then to defend their moral intuitions about the world which undergird their ways of life. Socratic inquiry deals not with producing a recitation of facts, or a questioning of the logic of various and sundry abstractions which are held up for comparison like in the Descartes method, but demands rather that the participants account for themselves, their thoughts, actions, and beliefs. The Socratic method functions as a dialectic approach to knowledge.
The Socratic Method focuses on moral education, on how one ought to live.[28] Socratic inquiry necessarily proceeds in an ad hominem style. That is, rather than making arguments or asking questions designed to convince any or all people, all comments in a Socratic inquiry are directed at specific participants in the discussion. Descartes inquiry is auto-inquiry. It is ego seeking fact. It is a rational search of new foundation of knowledge that is indubitable. Descartes posited:
This is why, as soon as age permitted me to emerge from the control of my tutors, I entirely quitted the study of letters. And resolving to seek no other science than that which could be found in myself…”[29] “I thus concluded that it is much more custom and example that persuade us than any certain knowledge, and yet in spite of this the voice of the majority does not afford a proof in truths a little difficult to discover, because such truths are much more likely to have been discovered by one man than by a nation.[30] 
Furthermore, the subject of inquiry of Socrates is not what is thought or said about the world in general, but what each participant thinks or says about the world.  The goal is not to consider depersonalized propositions and abstractions, but to probe the underlying values and beliefs of each inquirer. Since the substance of Socratic inquiry is the belief and value system of the participants, when those beliefs or values are challenged, or refuted, it is nothing less than the coherence of the lives of the people that is at stake. As Socrates says often in Plato’s dialogues, he is primarily concerned with how one ought to live. In Plato’s Gorgias, Socrates says, “Do not take what I say as if I were merely playing, for you see the subject of our discussion— and on what subject should even a man of slight intelligence be more serious?—namely, what kind of life should one live . . .”  Socrates is famous for saying “the unexamined life is not worth living.” Equally true, though less appreciated, is the fact that the unlived life is not worth examining.
A synthesis of the six parts of Discourse on the Method
In his Discourse on Method Rene Descartes’ attempts to explain his method of reasoning.  He uses philosophical arguments to illustrate the development of this method through a brief autobiographical sketch.  Discourse on the method was the first book published by Descartes in 1637.[31] The Discourse on Method is divided into six parts.  Each part deals with a specific idea. 
            In part one; he establishes the fact that good sense is the best universal shared endowment in the world.  According to him, it is evidence that the power of judging well and of telling the true from false which is what we properly call “good sense” or “reason’ is naturally equal in all; thus it is also evidence that our opinions differ not because some of us are more reasonable than others, but solely because we take our thoughts along different paths and do not attend to the same things.  If we all possess “good sense,” it is not a lack of ability that obstructs people but their failure to follow the correct path of thought.  The use of a method according to him can elevate an average mind above the rest. Descartes considers himself a typical thinker improved by the use of his method. He has no confidence in any of philosophy’s results, even in his own ability to improve that situation.  He comes to the conclusion that all people have a “natural light” that can be obscured by education and that it is as important to study oneself as it is to study the world. [32]
            In part two, Descartes holds that the works of individuals are superior to those conceived by committees, because an individual’s work follows one plan, with all elements working toward the same end. He opines that the sciences he learned in his younger days were confusing and complex because this consists of ideas of many different men from various eras.  Keeping in mind what he has learned of logic, geometrical analysis and Algebra, he sets down the following four main rules;
            First, was never to accept anything as true if he didn’t have evident knowledge of its truth. The second rule was to divide each of the difficulties he examined into as many parts as possible and as might be required in order to resolve them.         The third was to direct his thoughts in an orderly manner, by starting with the simplest and most easily known objects in order to move up gradually to knowledge of the most complex, and by stipulating some order even among objects that have no natural order of precedence. And the last was to make all his enumerations so complete, and many reviews so comprehensive, that he could be sure that he had not overlooked anything. Thus being afraid that his own misconceptions might be getting in the way of his pure reason, he decided to systematically do away with all his wrong opinions and use his new method exclusively.[33]
            In part three, Descartes while rethinking, puts up a provisional moral code consisting of four maxims, for according to him if you want to rebuild the house you live in, it is not enough just to pull it down, to arrange for materials and architects, and to have carefully drawn up the plans; you must also provide yourself with somewhere else to live comfortably while the work is going on.  So in order not to be indecisive in his actions, he sets forth the following moral codes;
            The first was to obey the laws and customs of his country, holding constantly to the religion in which by God’s grace he had been instructed from his childhood, and governing himself in all other matters. The second maxim was to be as firm and decisive in his actions as he could, and to follow even the most doubtful opinions, once he had adopted them, as constantly as if they had been quite certain. His third maxim was to try always to master himself rather than fortune and change his desires rather than changing how things stand in the world. Finally, to conclude this moral code, he decided to review the various occupations of human life, so as to try to choose the best. Without wanting to say anything about other people’s occupations, Descartes thought it would be best for him to continue with the very one he was then engaged in, and devote his whole life to cultivating his reason and advancing as far as he could in the knowledge of the truth, following his self-imposed method.  For Descartes, reasoning and searching for the truth is, if not the highest calling, at least extremely useful.
            Descartes distinguishes his method of doubting from that of skeptics, who doubt purely for the sake of doubting and pretends to be always indecisive; on the contrary, his whole aim was to reach certainty – to push away the loose earth and sand so as to get to rock or clay.  He concluded that he had pretty fair success in this, and pointed out three features of his procedure that contributed to its success: First, when trying to expose the falsity or uncertainty of any proposition, he brought arguments that were open and certain against it, not feeble conjectures. Second, he never encountered any proposition so doubtful that he could not get from it some fairly certain conclusion, even if it was only the conclusion that contained nothing certain. Third, in destroying all those opinions of his which he judged to be ill-founded he made various observations and acquired many experiences that he had since used in establishing more certain opinions. In search of certainty, Descartes travelled widely and finally retired to examine his thoughts in solitude.
            In part four, Descartes however, offered proofs of the existence of the soul and of God.  In contemplating the nature of dreams and the unreliability of the senses, he becomes aware of his own process of thinking – “I think therefore I exist” (Cogito ergo sum).  Thereby, admitting the limit of reason.  For his own doubt led him to believe that he is imperfect, yet his ability to conceive of perfection indicates that something perfect must exist outside of him – namely God.  He therefore reasons that all good things in the world must come from God, as must all clear and distinct thoughts.[34]
In the fifth part of this discourse, Descartes traces the long tradition, going back to Plato, which held that plants are special in having ‘vegetative souls’, lower animals in also having ‘sensitive souls’, and humans in having ‘rational souls’ as well as the other two.[35] He therefore describes a thought-experiment concerning a possible living human body which he takes not to be equipped with a rational soul or any substitute for one; he tacitly rules out the other kinds of soul as well, but allows that something in this human body namely, fire in the heart which he posited might play the role that earlier thinkers assigned to the vegetative and sensitive souls.
In the sixth part of this discourse, Descartes tries to outline the things he believes are needed if we are to go further than he has in the investigation of nature, and his reasons for writing this discourse.
Panel
Every child right from birth begins to learn, begins to learn how to talk, to walk, how to carry out some tasks, how to survive, he begins to learn how to fit in into the family and the society he or she finds himself or herself. To aid this process of learning the child is exposed to various forms of learning experiences, first at home, and then in school. At school, the child goes through a gradual and systematic process of growth and education. It is hoped that the child with time becomes fully educated and grounded on the basic principles of life, and that he or she becomes able to contribute to the growth and development of the nation. In fact, it has been rightly argued that education is the foundation on which any meaningful national development is built. Researches have shown and common sense tells us that the growth of all nations in the world is to a large extent directly proportional to the quality of education the citizens receive. It has been shown that developed countries  have a well-structured educational system, one that is capable of effectively contributing to the growth of the nation. Also, researches have shown that those countries that are referred to as less developed have a poor educational foundation. It is thus evident that no meaningful development can take place in the absence of an educational system that is of high quality.
 But what is education? Education has been defined as that which enables the individual to develop his capacities through the acquisition of knowledge, skills, attitudes and values; a process of developing the physical, social, mental and moral abilities of an individual; the process of teaching, preserving and upgrading culture in order to improve the welfare of man;  the deliberate, indirect and incidental experience one encounters as one passes through different phases or stages of life.[36]  Furthermore, the word “education” is derived from a Latin verb “educere” which means “to draw out”  “to bring forth” “to lead.” Thus it can be shown that the goal of education is to lead one to fully discover and harness one’s capabilities. But how do we do this? The usual way is that the pupil/student swallows all the teacher passes across, with little or no reflection on the part of the pupil/student.  Education is supposed to lead one inwards, to reflect, to question, to identify, to differentiate. What we have today is a form of education that is so much in a hurry, the teacher is in a hurry, the student is in a hurry. The student is not given the opportunity to critically examine the concepts and principles that abound in his or her area of study. There exists a form of dogmatism and authoritarianism to the extent that the student in some cases does not dare question the validity and relevance of some concepts. Can any meaningful development come from such a system of education? The great philosopher Socrates rightly captured this point many years ago when he said that “an unexamined life is not worth living” An education that is devoid of reflection is not worth the name and cannot meaningfully contribute to the growth and development of any nation. Rene Descartes however offers us a system of education, one that emphasizes a reflective mind.
Rene Descartes spent his mornings at the Jesuit school at La Fleche, France, in deep reflection. He was as a child diagnosed of mitochondria, and as a result was given a special dispensation from his morning duties in his school.[37] He converted those free times to moments of intense reflections, pondering on the nature of life and its ultimate value.[38] These reflections afforded him the opportunity to question the validity of his studies at La Fleche. Descartes considers the learner as his/her own teacher, noting that education is but a personal quest.[39] Thus, education should be student-centred, giving the student the opportunity to truly understand basic concepts and principles after of a rigorous and extensive process of questioning and doubting. Descartes maintained that for any meaningful learning to take place, it is important that the student doubts supposed truths; this will in the long run expand the horizons of the student and make him or her a better learner and a beret person, not one who just accepts without questioning the dictates of the teacher. This, for Descartes, will create a sense of creativity, originality and independence in the student. The student becomes a matured thinker capable of developing and maintaining intelligent arguments. This is the goal of education for Descartes as it will enable the proper acquisition of knowledge, one that will turn out to be a strong conviction that can never be shaken by any other. Descartes believed that truth can be learned by  a method of enquiry which entails doubting a supposed notion and reducing it into smaller and more basic units. This process is at the centre of any problem solving, and can be advantageous to any country which desires to grow and develop. From the above, it is evident that the old way of teaching and learning must give way to the new if our education system must make great impacts in our days.
 It is our position that the growth rate of Nigeria is low, that Nigeria is not fully harnessing her human and natural resource, that Nigeria is still far from what and where she wants to be. We posit further that the cause of this slow and low growth rate is largely due to the failure of her education system. We also posit that the education system has failed because of the abandonment of reflection, of deep, intense, matured and independent thinking in the whole ptocess of teaching and learning. It would seem that most Nigerians go to school out of compulsion. Little wonder it plays out in the way amd manner they approach learning. Every year our institutions of higher learning graduate students in their thousand, yet the nation keeps sinking in the mud of a snail-like growth .Every year, the National Youth Service Corps passes out young and vibrant men and women, yet our great nation swims in the shackles of abject poverty, despair, hunger, unemployment, corruption, just to mention but a few. The solution is simple, it is Cartesian in nature: an enthronement of a process of deep reflection as we go through the stages of formal and informal education. It is letting the school pass through us. It is doubting not for the sake of doubting but that one might come onto knowledge. It is a doubt that causes one to think, a thinking that opens one to newer ideas and ways of doing things, a thinking that spurs one to action, action that are solutions to the problems of today and those of tomorrow.  If Nigeria must grow, if she must take charge of the development of her resources both human and natural, it is our position that she must develop an education system that is student-centred, one that gives room for students to engage in reflection, that encourages enhancement, subjectivity, autonomy, creativity, originality. Students must be trained to become  matured and independent thinkers capable of contributing greatly to the growth of their nation.
Conclusion
            In this expose, we have shown Rene Descartes’ presentation of his method, a method he proposes for rightly conducting one’s reason and for seeking of truth. In this work, we found elements of Cartesian dualism and a treatment of his popular cogito ergo sum. The climax of the paper was our positon in the panel that the growth of any nation, Nigeria as a case study, cannot improve without a sound and reputable educational system. We also posited that no meaningful improvement can take place in the educational system if there is no emphasis on the student, on the promotion of the activity of reflection, of thinking on the part of the teacher, but especially on the part of the student..
While the presentation of Descartes’ method may seem very apt and rewarding, it is no doubt that there abounds varied and often opposing views to his position. A synthesis is thus necessary; this synthesis has occurred in various dimensions, the most prominent being the synthesis proposed by Immanuel Kant, the combination of reason and senses in the process of acquiring true and reliable knowledge. Research however continues in the various possible forms of this synthesis.





BIBLIOGRAPHY
Anthony Kenny, The Rise of Modern Philosophy (New York: Oxford University Press Inc., 2006)
Bell E. T. Men of Mathematics (New York, NY:  Simon & Schuster, Inc.,1937)
Bicknell  J, Descartes’ rhetoric: Roads, foundations, and difficulties in “The method, Philosophy & Rhetoric”, 2003, Volume 36(1), pp. 22-38.
Dario Composta, History of Ancient Philosophy (India: Theological Publications, 2008(
Dubey D L et al, An Introduction to Nigeria Education (Hong Kong: Macmillan, 1984)
Garrett Thomson, An Introduction to Modern Philosophy (California: Wadsworth Publishing Company, 1993)
James Seth, English Philosophers and Schools of Philosophy (New York: Ams Press Inc., 1973)
John Cottingham, The Cambridge Companion to Descartes (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1992)
Laurence Lafleur, Descartes’ Place in History in Rene Descartes, Discourse on Method (New York: The Bobbs-Merrill Company Inc., 1637)
Margaret Wilson, Descartes (Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1978), p. xiii-xiv.
Peter Angeles, Dictionary of Philosophy (New York: Harper and Row Publishers, Inc., 1981)
Rene Descartes, Discourse on Method (New York: The Bobbs-Merrill Company, Inc., 1637)
Samuel E. Stumpf, Philosophy: History and Problems (New York: Mc Graw-Hill Inc, 1994)
Robert Stoothoff et. al eds. Descartes: Selected Philosophical Writings (New York: Cambridge University Press 1998)
Spark Notes Editors, Spark Notes on René Descartes,. http://www.sparknotes.com/philosophy/descartes/ Accessed November 9, 2015
William F. Lawhead, The voyage of discovery; A historical introduction to philosophy (Belmont: Wadeworth/Thomson Learning Inc., 2002(
 http://www.sparksnotes.com/philosophy/discoursemethod/summary.htmt. Accessed on 10 Nov. 2015
http://www.sparknotes.com/philosophy/discoursemethod/summary.htmt.  Accessed on 11th  Nov. 2015



[1]  Cf. William F. Lawhead, The voyage of discovery; A historical introduction to philosophy (Belmont: Wadeworth/Thomson Learning Inc., 2002), p. 18.
[2] Cf. Samuel E. Stumpf,  Philosophy: History and Problems (New York: Mc Graw-Hill Inc, 1994), p. 13.
[3] Cf. Laurence Lafleur, Descartes’ Place in History in Rene Descartes, Discourse on Method (New York: The Bobbs-Merrill Company Inc., 1637), p. vii.
[4] Cf. John Cottingham, The Cambridge Companion to Descartes (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1992), p. 1
[5] Cf. Anthony Kenny, The Rise of Modern Philosophy (New York: Oxford University Press Inc., 2006), p. xiii
[6] Cf. Samuel E. Stumpf, Philosophy: History and Problem,  p. 236.
[7] John Cottingham, The Cambridge Companion to Descartes, p. 3.
[8] Cf. Rene Descartes, Discourse on Method (New York: The Bobbs-Merrill Company, Inc., 1637), p. 6.
[9] Cf. Samuel E. Stumpf, Philosophy: History and Problems, p. 237.
[10] Cf. John Cottingham, The Cambridge Companion to Descartes, pp. 4-5.
[11] Cf. Margaret Wilson, Descartes (Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1978), p. xiii-xiv.
[12] Cf. John Cottingham, The Cambridge Companion to Descartes, p. 4.
[13] Cf. Samuel E. Stumpf, Philosophy: History and Problems, p. 238.
[14] Cf.  Garrett Thomson, An Introduction to Modern Philosophy (California: Wadsworth Publishing Company, 1993), pp. 10-11.
[15] Cf. John Cottingham, The Cambridge Companion to Descartes, pp. 2-3.
[16]   Cf. Peter Angeles, Dictionary of Philosophy (New York: Harper and Row Publishers, Inc., 1981), p. 236.
[17]   Cf. Enoch Samuel Stumpf, Philosophy: History and Problems  p. 236.
[18]   Cf.James Seth, English Philosophers and Schools of Philosophy (New York: Ams Press Inc., 1973), p. 4.
[19]   Cf.Enoch Samuel Stumpf, Philosophy: History and Problems, p. 238.
[20]   Rene Descartes, Discourse on Method (New York: The Bobbs-Merrill Company, Inc., 1637), p.
[21] Peter Angeles, Dictionary of Philosophy p. 259.
[22] Cf. William F. Lawhead, The voyage of discovery- A historical introduction to philosophy (Belmont: Wadeworth/Thomson Learning Inc., 2002), p. 231-232.
[23] Cf. Spark Notes Editors, “Spark Note on René Descartes (1596–1650).” http://www.sparknotes.com/philosophy/descartes/ Accessed November 9, 2015
[24] Cf. Rene Descartes, Discourse on Method, p.13 
[25] Cf. Rene Descartes, Discourse on method, p. 18
[26] Cf. Dario Composta, History of Ancient Philosophy,(India: Theological Publications, 2008), p.114
[27] CF. Dario Composta, History of Ancient Philosophy, p.117
[28] CF. Dario Composta, History of Ancient Philosophy, p.117
[29] Cf. Rene Descartes, Discourse on Method, p. 30
[30] Cf. Rene Descartes, Discourse on Method, p. 35

[31] Cf. Robert Stoothoff et. al eds. Descartes: Selected Philosophical Writings (New York: Cambridge University Press 1998), p. ii.

[34] Cf. http://www.sparknotes.com/philosophy/discoursemethod/summary.htmt.  Accessed on 11th  Nov. 2015
[35] Cf. Rene Descartes, Discourse on Method, p. 30
                                     





[36]   Cf. Dubey D L et al, An Introduction to Nigeria Education (Hong Kong: Macmillan, 1984), pp. 1-2.
[37] Cf. Rene Descartes, Discourse on Method, p. xi
[38] Cf. Bell, E. T. Men of Mathematics.( New York, NY:  Simon & Schuster, Inc., 1937), p.45
[39] Cf. Bicknell, J.  ().  Descartes’ rhetoric: Roads, foundations, and difficulties in “The method, Philosophy & Rhetoric”, 2003, Vol 36(1), pp. 22-38.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

SUMMARY OF PROVIDENTISSIMUS DEUS, ENCYCLICAL LETTER OF POPE LEO XIII ON THE STUDY OF THE HOLY SCRIPTURE.

summary and appraisal of chapters one, two and three of the book The African Origin of Greek Philosophy: An Exercise in Afrocentrism, by Innocent C. Onyewuenyi.

THE LAST THREE WAYS TO PROVES GOD'S EXISTENCE BY THOMAS AQUINAS