Malcolm Budd on Delight in the Natural World: An Understanding of Kant on the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature.


Review of Malcolm Budd on Delight in the Natural World: An Understanding of Kant on the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature.
Introduction
            Aesthetic is a philosophical inquiry or investigation into the field of art and its creative imaginative work. It is sometimes called, philosophy of art, because it attempts to know the nature, scope, limitation, and critical analysis and judgement of the work of art. In assessing what should be the nature and scope of Aesthetic, philosophers right from antiquity to modern era define what Aesthetic is. Beginning with Plato understanding of Aesthetic……this is to recall what aesthetic means and different views concerning its nature and scope.
Malcolm Budd wrote an article concerning the views of Immanuel Kant’s work in a British Journal of Aesthetics titled “Delight in the Natural World: Kant on the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature. Though his approach or methodology is good, beginning from exposition of Kant’s view; meaning of pure aesthetic judgement, types and mathematical measurement of Magnitude, thereafter his gave his own view and then conclusion. So in this paper, we shall review what Malcolm said about Kant and his own contribution, further, we shall attempt a bit of criticism of the article.
General Overview of Kant’s Idea in Malcolm
            In knowing what an aesthetic judgement of sublime nature could contain, Kant asserted that, pure aesthetic judgement of the sublime is a singular, categorical judgement that is not based on an interest in or a concept of the object it is occasioned by.[1] Since perception is use as the main tool in analysing and judging aesthetic object, but Kant’s fundamental thought about the sublime in nature is that, sublimity cannot properly be predicated of any natural object.[2] Because, for Kant ‘sublime’ is a term of approval, but in itself an object that precipitates the feeling of the sublime and it is experienced as contrapurposive for ourselves as embodied subjects, appearing incommensurate with our sensory or physical powers, and as it were violating our imagination, that is, such object induces in us a feeling of sublimity as well as to make us know that we are sublime as a rational agent. Therefore, since the feeling of our own sublimity is pleasurable, and this movement of our mind which is provoked by the sublime nature must in some way be subjectively purposive.[3]
              This rational reaction of sublime nature generates two forms of sublime: first, the mathematically sublime and second, dynamically sublime. And these two forms of the sublime involve: (1) an estimation or (awareness) of nature’s immensity, (2) an operation of the imagination, (3) a felt inadequacy in our power with respect to nature, and (4) a compensating superiority over nature.[4]
Measurement of Mathematical Sublimity
Mathematically sublime according to Kant is absolutely great or large, great beyond all comparison. This definition is based on a distinction between two ways of estimating or judging an object’s size; either an aesthetic estimation or a mathematical estimation of magnitude.[5] For aesthetic estimation of magnitude is made by the eye without the aid of measuring instruments, on the basis of the object’s appearance in mere intuition. Further, Kant claimed that, all estimation of the magnitude of natural objects ultimately aesthetic, namely the most that can be grasped in a single intuition. For instance, spatial objects are extensive magnitudes, and so can be intuited only through successive synthesis of part to part.[6] And this is done through apprehension and comprehension of the object. Though apprehension can be ad infinitum but comprehension of an object has a maximum point one can reach. Also to estimate the size of an object aesthetically, it must be possible to comprehend it or grasp, hold together in a single intuition.[7]
In having an aesthetic estimation of an object’s size, it must consist of distance and condition concerning light, since the magnitude of any object is in principle available as an aesthetic unit of measure. So the larger the object the magnitude of which is to be estimated aesthetically the larger must the unit of measure be. Malcolm added that, an aesthetic estimate of magnitude involves the choice of a certain unit of measure and an estimate by sight of the magnitude of the given object as a certain multiple of this unit. So the larger the object, the larger the unit of measure required to estimate its magnitude by sight.[8]
Dynamically Sublime
            These are displays of natural phenomena such like power of a hurricane, a tidal wave, an erupting volcano, a bolt of lightning, the tumultuous ocean, the high waterfall of a mighty river. In resisting these phenomena in nature, human possess two powers: (1) the physical power, which is puny in comparison with the might of certain natural phenomena, whose force is such as to overwhelm and destroy us, and (2) the power not to abandon our moral principles and commitment to morality, even under the greatest pressure. With the respect of this nature has no dominion over us, because we are capable of regarding all worldly goods, our health and even our life. In essence though, we are subject to nature’s might with respect to our self-preservation as physical beings but not as moral beings.[9]  
            To judge nature as being dynamically sublime it must be thought of as something that we would be physically unable to resist the might of, and so as fearful, an object to fear but in judging it,  we must not actually be afraid of what we judge to be sublime. Another to judge dynamically sublime nature is through imagination. This help to us to know even not certain the degree of its power.[10]
The Meaning of Sublime Nature
            With all these analysis of sublime nature and the forms in which it could be assessed, Kant believed that, sublime nature is an emotion with a complex phenomenology, possessing both a twofold hedonic reaction and a twofold thought content, the two hedonic reactions having opposite signs, the negative leading to the positive, the first involving repulsion from the perceived object, while the second attraction to it. The negative component of the feeling of the sublime is an unpleasant awareness of the inadequacy of our sensory or physical power to construct an adequate aesthetic unit of measure which can be taken in one intuition and suitable for an estimation of the infinite.[11]
For Malcolm, rather than identifying this pain of natural phenomenon or magnitude, in the experience of the mathematically sublime, as rising from the imagination’s fruitless struggle to come up with a accurate measure, it is a clear realization of our relative insignificance in the immense order of nature.[12] And on the other hand, this pain could be view to originate from heightening of the sense of our vulnerability to nature’s power when we are faced by and imagine ourselves being subjected to it. Hence, looking at both cases, the sense of our being in the world that tends to inform the way in which we live our life is disrupted.[13]
            Malcolm pointed out the fault in Kant’s aesthetic judgements about the sublimity of natural objects. For him, if there should be any pure aesthetic judgement, it should not base on concepts especially when it comes to purposes they have in nature. Another one is that, he does not think that, Kant should represent sublime in nature as being a judgement occasioned by the boundlessness, the immensity of matter or power as these appear to us in perception. So for him, pure aesthetic judgement about the sublimity of nature must be used on the intrinsic character of a natural object’s or phenomenon’s sensible intuition or image.[14]  
Critic of Malcolm Budd’s Position    

                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                     


[1] Malcolm Budd, “Delight in the Natural World: Kant on the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature” in British Journal of Aesthetic, Vol. 38, No. 3, (July 1998), p. 233
[2] Malcolm Budd, “Delight in the Natural World: Kant on the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature” in British Journal of Aesthetic, p.233
[3] Malcolm Budd, “Delight in the Natural World: Kant on the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature” in British Journal of Aesthetic, p.233
[4] Malcolm Budd, “Delight in the Natural World: Kant on the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature” in British Journal of Aesthetic, pp.233-234
[5] Malcolm Budd, “Delight in the Natural World: Kant on the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature” in British Journal of Aesthetic, p.234

[6] Malcolm Budd, “Delight in the Natural World: Kant on the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature” in British Journal of Aesthetic, pp. 234-235
[7] Malcolm Budd, “Delight in the Natural World: Kant on the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature” in British Journal of Aesthetic, p.235-236
[8] Malcolm Budd, “Delight in the Natural World: Kant on the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature” in British Journal of Aesthetic, p.237-238

[9] Malcolm Budd, “Delight in the Natural World: Kant on the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature” in British Journal of Aesthetic, p. 241
[10] Malcolm Budd, “Delight in the Natural World: Kant on the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature” in British Journal of Aesthetic, p.242
[11] Malcolm Budd, “Delight in the Natural World: Kant on the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature” in British Journal of Aesthetic, p. 244

[12] Malcolm Budd, “Delight in the Natural World: Kant on the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature” in British Journal of Aesthetic, p.245
[13] Malcolm Budd, “Delight in the Natural World: Kant on the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature” in British Journal of Aesthetic, p.245
[14] Malcolm Budd, “Delight in the Natural World: Kant on the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature” in British Journal of Aesthetic, p.247


Comments

Popular posts from this blog

SUMMARY OF PROVIDENTISSIMUS DEUS, ENCYCLICAL LETTER OF POPE LEO XIII ON THE STUDY OF THE HOLY SCRIPTURE.

summary and appraisal of chapters one, two and three of the book The African Origin of Greek Philosophy: An Exercise in Afrocentrism, by Innocent C. Onyewuenyi.

THE LAST THREE WAYS TO PROVES GOD'S EXISTENCE BY THOMAS AQUINAS