moral objectivism, moral absolutivism and theory of double effect,
Moral objectivism:
There
are objective universal moral principles, valid for all people and all social
environments.
Moral absolutism.
The absolutist believes that there are non overrideable moral principles that
one ought never violate. Moral principles are exceptionless. For example, some
absolutists hold that one ought never break a promise, no matter what. The
objectivist shares with the absolutist the notion that moral principles have
universal, objective validity. However, objectivists deny that moral norms are
necessarily exceptionless. The objectivist could believe that no moral duty has
absolute weight or strict priority; each moral principle must be weighed
against other moral principles in special situations, one moral duty might be
overridden by a different and more compelling duty. For example, the duty to
tell the truth might be overridden in a situation where speaking the truth
would lead to serious harm. In this case, the duty to avoid harm would override
the duty to tell the truth.
Natural
law theory is the view that there exists an eternal moral law that can be
discovered through reason by looking at the nature of humanity and society. The
whole universe is governed by laws that exhibit rationality. Nature in general
and animals in particular obey these laws by necessity, but humans have a
choice. Humans obey these laws because they can perceive the laws’ inner
reasonableness.
Aquinas
combied Humanity’s essence or proper function is to live the life of reason.
As
Aristotle put it: Reason is the true self of every man, since it is the supreme
and better part. It will be strange, then, if he should choose not his own
life, but some other’s. What is naturally proper to every creature is the
highest and pleasantest for him. And so, to man, this will be the life of
Reason,
since
Reason is, in the highest sense, a man’s self. 2
Humanity’s
function is to exhibit rationality in all its forms: contemplation,
deliberation, and action. For Aquinas, reason’s deliberative processes discover
the natural laws. They are universal rules, or “ordinances of reason for the
common good, spread by him who has the care of the community” Therefore, the
order of the precepts of the natural law is according to the order of natural
inclinations.
The
key ideas of the natural law tradition are the following:
1.
Human beings have an essential rational nature established by God, who designed
us to live and flourish in prescribed ways (from Aristotle and the Stoics).
2.
Even without knowledge of God, reason, as the essence of our nature, can discover
the laws necessary for human flourishing (from Aristotle; developed by
Aquinas).
3.
The natural laws are universal and unchangeable, and one should use them to
judge individual societies and their positive laws. Positive (or actual) laws of
societies that are not in line with the natural law are not truly laws but counterfeits
(from the Stoics).
The Doctrine of Double Effect
Aquinas’s
position is not only objectivist but also absolutist. But, sometimes we
encounter moral conflicts, “dilemmas” in which we cannot do good without also
bringing about evil consequences. To this end, Aquinas devised the doctrine of
double effect (DDE), which provides a tidy method for solving all moral
disputes in which an act will have two effects, one good and the other bad.
The
doctrine says, roughly, that it is always wrong to do a bad act intentionally
in order to bring about good consequences, but that it is sometimes permissible
to do a good act despite knowing that it will bring about bad consequences.
This doctrine consists in four conditions that must be satisfied before an act
is morally permissible:
1.
The nature-of-the-act condition. The action must be either morally good or
indifferent. Lying or intentionally killing an innocent person is never
permissible. E.g. Abortion, Terrorist bombing (not strategic bombing except one
like Hiroshima and Nagasaki)
2.
The means–end condition. The bad effect must not be the means by which one
achieves the good effect.
3.
The right-intention condition. The intention must be the achieving of only the
good effect, with the bad effect being only an unintended side effect. If the
bad effect is a means of obtaining the good effect, then the act is immoral.
The bad effect may be foreseen but must not be intended.
4.
The proportionality condition. . The good effect must be at least equivalent in
importance to the bad effect.
The
Roman Catholic Church uses this doctrine to prohibit not only most abortions
but also the use of contraceptives. Because the procreation of life is good and
the frustration of life is bad and because the natural purpose of sexual
intercourse is to produce new life, it is wrong to use devices that prevent
intercourse from producing its natural result.
Consider
another example. Suppose that Sally’s father has planted a nuclear bomb that
will detonate in a half hour. Sally is the only person who knows where he hid
it, and she has promised him that’s he will not reveal the location to anyone.
Although she regrets his act, as a devoted daughter she refuses to break her
promise and give away the secret. However, if we do not discover where the bomb
is and dismantle it within the next half hour, it will blow up a city and kill
a million people. Suppose we can torture Sally to get this information from her.
According to the DDE, is this permissible? No, for the end does not justify the
means. Condition 2 is violated. We are using a bad act to bring about a good
effect.
Comments
Post a Comment