Objections to the possibility of motion


Objections to the possibility of motion
            Parmenides objection to motion
            The philosopher Parmenides was among the first sets is philosophers who objected to the possibility of any things such as motion. He was born about 510 BC, and lived most of his life at Elea, southwest of Italy. He rejected the common sense notion of change by his distinction between appearance and reality. Change, he said, is the most confusion of appearance with reality and therefore change is simply an Illusion.[1]
            Parmenides started that motion is a passage from being to non-being and vice versa. He further stated that, non-being is impossible. Therefore, motion is impossible. In response, Aristotle argued that motion is a passage from being secundum quid (in a certain sense) to non-being secundum quid and vice versa; however, it is not a passage from being simplicitor (in an absolutely sense) to non-being simplicitor and vice versa. He said that motion is a passage from potential being to actual being. When a thing that is in potency is moved to act, it receives a new modification of what is in existence throughout the motion.
Responding further to the objections raised by Parmenides, Aristotle stated that the existence of non-being simplicitor is impossible, but the existence of non0being secundum quid is possible. It is certainly impossible for a substance both to exist and not to exist at the same time, but it is not impossible to lack a certain form and hence to be non-being secundum quid.in a certain respect.[2]
            Summarily, this is Parmenides’ objection: “what is, cannot come to be (since already is); while nothing can come to be from what is not.”
The idea of this argument seems to be this: it is a case of coming to be, the resulting object is clearly a being, something that is. From what initial object doles it come to be? If the initial object is what is and the resultant object is also what is, we do not really have a case of coming to be. There is no change or motion. And if the mind object is what is not, we have another kind of impossibility for nothing can come to be from what is not.
            Aristotle rejected Parmenides’ dilemma that something comes to be from what is, or from what is not.[3] He does so systematically by drawing a distinction between the two senses of “coming to be.” Is the initial object a being or a non-being: Parmenides asks? Aristotle answers: in a way it is not a being. And in a way it is not a being and in a way it is not a non-being. The initial object might be an unmusical man. This, in one way is a being and in another way a non-being. The initial object is something (for it is a man) and something that is not (for it is not musical). Aristotle agrees with Parmenides that nothing comes to be out of cheer nothingness but he also maintain that, in a sense, things can come to be in a way. For instance, coincidentally from what is not. Something can come to be from the privation, which in itself is not, and does belong to the thing.
            Note here that, the ‘music-ness’ comes to be from the compound unmusical man. What he comes to be from is in one way a non-being, since he comes to be from a privation, the ‘unmusic-ness’ or unmusical. But in a way, what he comes to be from is a being as well, for the initial object (man) is something that exists. Thus Parmenides offers us a false dilemma that the initial object is either being or not being but since the initial object is a compound, in a way it is both.
Zeno’s objection to the possibility of motion
Zeno was a student of Parmenides. He was born in Elea about 489 BC. In a bid to defend the position of his master Parmenides, that motion and change do not occur, he proposed his four paradoxes.  
The first is the dichotomy paradox. It states that to get to any point, we must first travel halfway, and to get to that halfway point, we must travel half of that halfway, and to get to that half of the halfway, we must first travel a half of the half of that halfway and infinitely, so that, for any given instance there is always a smaller distance to be covered first. And so, we can never start moving at all. Aristotle answered that, time can be divided just as infinitely as space, so that it would have infinitely little time to cover the infinitely little space needed to get started, therefore there is the possibility of motion.
The second paradox is known as the Achilles paradox. It states that, supposing Achilles is racing a tortoise, and gives the tortoise and gives the tortoise a head start. Then by the time  Achilles reaches the point the started from, the tortoise will have advanced a certain distance and by the point Achilles covers that certain distance the tortoise will have advance a bit farther, and so on, so that it seems Achilles will never be able to catch up with, let alone pass the tortoise. Thus, motion is not taking place.
Aristotle responded that the paradox assumes the existence of an actual infinity of parts between Achilles and the tortoise. If there were an actual infinity –that is, if Achilles has had to take account of all the infinite points, he passed in catching up with the tortoise – it would indeed take infinite account of time for Achilles to pass the tortoise. However, there is only a potential infinite, of course, between Achilles and the tortoise, meaning that Achilles can cover the infinitely many points between him and the tortoise in a finite amount of time so long as he does not have another account of each point along the way.
The third paradox is called the Arrow paradox. It states that, an arrow at flight is really at rest. For every point in the flight, the arrow must occupy a length of space exactly equal to its own. After all, it cannot occupy a greater length, nor a lesser one. But the arrow cannot ………this length it occupies. It would need exactly the same space in which to move and it of course has none. So at every point in its flight, the arrow is at rest. And if it is at rest at every moment in its flight, then it follows then that, it is at rest during the entire flight.
Aristotle answered that it does not follow that the arrow does not move at all. The concept of motion can simply be understood as occupying different parts of space at different points in time.[4]    
The forth paradox is called the stadium paradox. It concerns equal bodies which alongside equal bodies in the stadium from opposite direction- the ones from the end of the stadium, the others from the middle, at equal speeds. Zeno drew from this that half the time is equal to its double.
This is a rather obscure paradox, but Aristotle posited that the fallacy inherent in this paradox consists in requiring that a body travelling at equal speed travels for an equal time past a moving body and a body of the same size at rest. He argued that how long it takes to pass a body depends on the speed of the body.[5]
Conclusion
In this paper, we have attempted to understand the meanings of nature and motion. We critically analyzed the meaning of nature and motion, the various categories of motion, the three species of motion. This paper was aimed at an examination of Parmenides’ and Zeno’s objections to the possibility of motion and Aristotle’s responses to these objections.   

Thomas Aquinas, commenting on Aristotle's objection, wrote "Instants are not parts of time, for time is not made up of instants any more than a magnitude is made of points, as we have already proved. Hence it does not follow that a thing is not in motion in a given time, just because it is not in motion in any instant of that time. [6] 
Before 212 BC, Archimedes had developed a method to derive a finite answer for the sum of infinitely many terms that get progressively smaller. (See: Geometric series, 1/4 + 1/16 + 1/64 + 1/256 + · · ·, The Quadrature of the Parabola.) Modern calculus achieves the same result, using more rigorous methods (see convergent series, where the "reciprocals of powers of 2" series, equivalent to the Dichotomy Paradox, is listed as convergent). These methods allow the construction of solutions based on the conditions stipulated by Zeno, i.e. the amount of time taken at each step is geometrically decreasing.[7]
Bertrand Russell offered what is known as the "at-at theory of motion". It agrees that there can be no motion "during" a durationless instant, and contends that all that is required for motion is that the arrow be at one point at one time, at another point another time, and at appropriate points between those two points for intervening times. In this view motion is a function of position with respect to time.[8]     
Nick Huggett argues that Zeno is begging the question when he says that objects that occupy the same space as they do at rest must be at rest.[9]    
Philosophical Relevance    
Contemporary Import
            Despite the fact that the positions of Parmenides and Zeno were denying the subject matter of the study of nature, that is, denying the starting point of the science of nature;
 It is also an undeniable fact that, these objections helped Aristotle to establish a solid foundation the this same subject matter (motion) and the science of nature as a whole.


[1] Samuel stumpf, philosophy, history and problem…………………p. 16-18.
[2] Aristotle, physics, book I, 191, p.232-236.
[3] Aristotle, 191 a 30.
[4] Aristotle, bk vi, 239 b 33-2, 40a 5.
[5] Aristotle, bk.vi, 240.
[6] Aquinas. Commentary on Aristotle's Physics, Book 6.861.
[7] George B. Thomas, Calculus and Analytic Geometry, Addison Wesley, 1951.
Boyer, Carl (1959). The History of the Calculus and Its Conceptual Development. Dover Publications. p. 295. ISBN 978-0-486-60509-8. Retrieved 2010-02-26. "If the paradoxes are thus stated in the precise mathematical terminology of continuous variables (...) the seeming contradictions resolve themselves."
[8] Huggett, Nick (1999). Space From Zeno to Einstein. ISBN 0-262-08271-3.
[9] Huggett, Nick (2010). "Zeno's Paradoxes: 3.3 The Arrow". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2011-03-07.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

SUMMARY OF PROVIDENTISSIMUS DEUS, ENCYCLICAL LETTER OF POPE LEO XIII ON THE STUDY OF THE HOLY SCRIPTURE.

summary and appraisal of chapters one, two and three of the book The African Origin of Greek Philosophy: An Exercise in Afrocentrism, by Innocent C. Onyewuenyi.

THE LAST THREE WAYS TO PROVES GOD'S EXISTENCE BY THOMAS AQUINAS