philosophy of language, linguistics and linguistic philosophy


Introduction
Language is a veritable instrument of thought and communication. This thought cannot be communicated properly without using a right language. Because our thought is invisible and in order to bring people to the world of our idea that is contain in our mind we need to have a medium by which we use in disseminating the idea so that our audience can truly understand what we have communicated. Communication entails the use of language and language is made with words. As Locke rightly asserted that, words are sensible marks of idea. And the ideas this word stand for are proper and immediate significant. Ideas are in thought while word is language use to express what is in our mind.[1]
To better express the ideas that contain in our mind, philosophers of language preoccupy themselves in examine what the meaning of a statement uttered by individual. Whether they actually mean what they have in mind and at the same time to see if the audience really comprehend the message communicated. Further philosophers of language then discover that, often time people misrepresent the ideas in their mind because they lack proper word and proper construction of the statement. Here linguistic arose to give a guard on how we can combine words together in order to fit what we intend to communicate to our audience. Not only how to combine to suit our ideas, rather linguistic philosophy emphases on indication of our ideas in the world of experience. That there should be a reference to everything we say. At this point we then have analytic philosopher and positivist. For them, language can best be understood using facts, not idea that abstracts statement.
Therefore at this point, we shall examine the stands of philosophy of language, linguistics and linguistic philosophy. In doing this we shall consider their nature (through conceptual clarification), issues, and problem, further their similarities (relationships) and differences.      
Conceptual Clarification
            What do we mean by the term “Linguistic”? Linguistic can be defined as the scientific study of language.[2] Such study has, broadly speaking, three aspects: language form, language meaning, and language in context.[3] The earliest known activities in the description of language have been attributed to Panini with his analysis of Sanskritin Ashtadhyayi.[4] Panini was a Sanskrit grammarian from ancient India.[5] Linguistics analysis human language as a system for relating sounds or signed gesture and meaning.[6]
Some Aspects of Linguistic
·         Phonetics: this an aspect that study acoustic and articulatory properties of the production and perception of speech sounds and non-speech sounds. The study of language meaning, on the other hand, deals with how languages encode relations between entities, properties, and other aspects of the world to convey, process, and assign meaning, as well as to manage and resolve ambiguity.
·         Semantics: this aspect typically concerns itself with truth conditions, pragmatics deals with how the context influences meanings.[7]
·         Grammar: grammar comprises the system of rules which governs the form of the utterances in a given language. It encompasses both sound and meaning, and includes phonology (which is how sounds function and pattern together), morphology (the formation and composition of words), and syntax (the formation and composition of phrases and sentences from these words).[8]
Type of Grammar
·         Phonology: this is a branch of linguistics concerned with the systematic organization of sounds in languages. It has traditionally focused largely on the study of the systems of phonemes in particular languages but it may also cover any linguistic analysis either at a level beneath the word or at all levels of language where sound is considered to be structured for conveying linguistic meaning. Phonology is often distinguished from phonetics. While phonetics concerns the physical production, acoustic transmission and perception of the sounds of speech.[9] Phonology describes the way sounds function within a given language or across languages to encode meaning. For many linguists, phonetics belongs to descriptive linguistics, and phonology to theoretical linguistics, although establishing the phonological system of a language is necessarily an application of theoretical principles to analysis of phonetic evidence.[10]
·         Morphology: in linguistic, morphology is the identification, analysis, and description of the structure of a given language’s morphemes and other linguistic units, such as root words, affixes, parts of speech, intonations and stresses, or implied context. In contrast, morphology typology is the classification of languages according to their use of morphemes, while lexicology is the study of those words forming a language’s word-stock. It is possible to use the concept of functions to describe more than just how lexical meanings work: they can also be used to describe the meaning of a sentence. For instance, the sentence “the horse is red”. We may consider “the horse” to be the product of a propositional function.
A propositional function is an operation of language that takes an entity as an input and outputs a semantic fact. That is, the proposition that is represented by “the horse is red”. In other words, a propositional function is like an algorithm. The meaning of “red” in this case is whatever takes the entity “the horse” and turns it inot the statement, “the horse is red”.[11] Along with clitics (clitics means, a morpheme that has syntactic characteristics of a word, but depends phonologically on another word or phrase)[12] are generally accepted as being the smallest units of syntax. In most languages, if not all, many words can be related to other words by rules that collectively describe the grammar for that language. Therefore, morphology is the branch of linguistics that studies patterns of word formation within and across languages and attempts to formulate rules that model the knowledge of the speakers of those languages.
·         Syntax: this is the study of principles and processes by which sentences are constructed in particular languages.[13] Syntax is also used to refer directly to the rules and principles that govern the sentence structure of any individual language. These rules also extend in governing the behaviour of mathematical system, such as formal languages used in logic. However, many aspects of the problem of the composition of sentences are addressed in the field of linguistics of syntax. For philosophical semantics tends to focus on the principle of compositionality to explain the relationship between meaningful parts and whole sentences. The principle of compositionality asserts that, a sentence can be understood on the basis of the meaning of the parts of the sentence (that is word, morphemes) along with an understanding of its structure (that is syntax and logic).[14]
Having considered the aspects of linguistic, Ferdinand de Saussure in the early 20th century distinguished between the notions of langue and parole. In his formulation of structural and linguistics, he said, parole is the specific utterance of speech, whereas langue refers to an abstract phenomenon that theoretically defines the principles and system of rules that govern a language.[15]  This distinction can be likened to Noam Chomsky’s competence and performance. In which, competence is said to be an individual’s ideal knowledge of a language, while performance is the specific way in which it is used.[16]
Types of Linguistics
·         Psycholinguistics: this kind of linguistics explores the representation and function of language in the mind.
·         Neurolinguistics: this is the study of language processing in the brain and language acquisition which investigates how children and adults acquire a particular language.
·         Sociolinguistics: linguistics also includes non-formal approaches to the study of other aspects of human language, such as social, cultural, historical and political factors, majorly is the concern of sociolinguistic.[17] This type of linguistics looks at the relation between linguistic variation and social structures, as well as that of discourse analysis, which examines the structure of texts and conversation. Research on language through historical and evolutionary linguistics focuses on how languages change, and on the origin and growth of growth of languages, particularly over an extended period of time.
·         Corpus linguistics: this type of linguistics takes naturally occurring texts as its primary object of analysis, and studies the variation of grammatical and other features based on such corpora. Under this kind of linguistics we have style. The stylistics involves the study of patterns of style: within written as well as within spoken discourse.[18] Whereas language documentation combines anthropological inquiry with linguistic inquiry to describe languages and their grammars. Also lexicography covers the study and construction of dictionaries.
·         Computational linguistics: this applies computer technology to address questions in theoretical linguistics, as well as to create applications for use in parsing, data retrieval, machine translation, and other areas.
Linguistic Philosophy
            Linguistic philosophy describes the view that philosophical problems are problems which may be solved either by reforming language, or by understanding more about the language we presently use.[19] The history of the philosophy of language in the analytical tradition begins with advances in logic and with tensions within traditional accounts of the mind and its contents at the end of the nineteenth century. A revolution of sorts resulted from these developments, often known as the "Linguistic Turn" in philosophy. Much of the stage-setting for the so-called "Linguistic Turn" in Anglo-American philosophy took place in the mid nineteenth century. Attention turned to language as many came to see it as a focal point in understanding belief and representation of the world. Language came to be seen as the "medium of conceptualization," as Wilfrid Sellars would later put it. [20]
Idealists working in Kant's wake had developed more sophisticated "transcendental" accounts of the conditions for the possibility of experience, and this evoked strong reactions from more realist philosophers and those sympathetic to the natural sciences. Scientists also made advances in the 1860s and 70s in describing cognitive functions like speech production and comprehension as natural phenomena, including the discovery of Broca's area and Wernicke's area, two neural centers of linguistic activity. Mill's empiricism led him to think that for meaning to have any significance for our thought and understanding, we must explain it in terms of our experience. Thus, meaning should ultimately be understood in terms of words standing for sets of sense impressions.[21]
Not all those concerned with language shared Mill's empiricist leanings, though most shared his sense that denotation, rather than connotation, should be at the center of an account of meaning. A word denotes something by standing for it, as my name stands for me, or "Baltimore" stands for a particular city on America's East Coast; a word connotes something when it "implies an attribute" in Mill's terms, as "professor" generally implies an expert in an academic field and someone with certain sorts of institutional authority.[22] Thus,
(1) The cat sat on the refrigerator.
should be understood as a complex arrangement of signs. "The cat" denotes or refers to a particular furry domesticated quadruped, "the refrigerator" denotes something, and so forth. Some further elaboration would be needed for verbs, logical vocabulary and other categories of terms, but most philosophers took the backbone of an account of meaning to be denotation, and language use to be a process of the management of signs. These signs might denote objects directly, or they might do so indirectly by standing for something within our minds, following Locke, who described words as "signs of ideas".[23]
Problem: Accounts that emphasized the reference of terms as constitutive of the meaning of most expressions faced two serious problems, however. First, they failed to explain the possibility of non-referring terms and negative existential sentences. On such a referential picture of meaning, the meaning of most expressions would simply be their bearers, so an existential sentence like
(1) John Coltrane plays saxophone. was easy to analyze. Its subject term, "John Coltrane," referred to a particular person and the sentence says of him that he does a particular sort of thing: he plays saxophone. But what of a sentence like
(2) Phlogiston was thought to be the cause of combustion.
Assuming that there is not and never was such a thing as phlogiston, how can we understand such a sentence? If the meaning of those expressions is their referent, then this sentence should strike us as meaningless.
            The second serious problem for referential theories of meaning, noted by Frege, was the informativeness of some identity sentences. Sentences of self-identity are true purely in virtue of their logical form, and we may affirm them even when we do not know what the expression refers to.[24] For instance, anyone could affirm
(3) Mt. Kilimanjaro is Mt. Kilimanjaro.
even if they do not know what Mt. Kilimanjaro is. Making this statement in such a case would not inform our understanding of the world in any significant way. However, a sentence like
(4) Mt. Kilimanjaro is the tallest mountain in Africa.
would certainly be informative to those who first heard it. But remember that according to referential theories of meaning, "Mt. Kilimanjaro" and "the tallest mountain in Africa" refer to the same thing and hence mean the same thing according to these theories; therefore, (3) and (4) say the same thing and one should be no more or less informative than the other. Where we grasp the meaning of an expression or a sentence, philosophers have traditionally taken it that this should make some sort of cognitive difference, for example, we should be able to perform an action, make an inference, recognize something, and so on. Thus differences in the meanings of expressions should be reflected by some difference in cognitive significance between the expressions. But if expressions refer to the same thing, and their meaning consists solely in their picking out a referent, then there should be no such cognitive difference even if there is apparently a difference in meaning. Simple referential theories do not offer us an obvious solution to this problem and therefore fail to capture important intuitions about meaning.[25]
            To address these problems, Frege proposed that we should think of expressions as having two semantic aspects: a sense and a reference. Rudolf Carnap would later replace the term "sense" with "intension" and "reference" with "extension."[26]  The sense of an expression would be its "mode of presentation," as Frege put it, that conveyed information to us in its own distinct way. That information would in turn determine a referent for each expression. This led to a credo pervasive in analytical philosophy: sense determines reference. This solved problems of reference by shifting the emphasis to the sense of expressions first and to their reference later.[27] Negative existential sentences were intelligible because the sense of an expression like "largest prime number" or "Atlantis" could be logically analyzed or made explicit in terms of other descriptions, even if the set of things specified by this information was, in fact, empty. Our belief that these sentences and expressions were meaningful was a consequence of grasping their senses, even when we realized this left them without a referent. However, Russell wondered how
(9) The present King of France is bald.
could be meaningful, given the absence of a present King of France. Russell's solution was to analyze the logical role of such descriptions. Although a select few expressions referred directly to objects, most were either descriptions that picked out a referent by offering a list of properties, or disguised abbreviations of such descriptions. Russell even suggested that most proper names were abbreviated descriptions. Strictly speaking, descriptions would not refer at all; they would be quantified phrases that had or lacked extensions.[28]
Philosophy of Language
Philosophy of language is concerned with four central problems: the nature of meaning, language use, language cognition, and the relationship between language and reality. For the continental philosophers, however, the philosophy of language tends to be dealt with, not as a separate topic, but as a part of logic. This an approach to philosophical problems used especially by certain British and American philosophers, inspired by G. E. Moore, and marked by the elucidation of difficult and controversial concepts by resolving them into their elements.[29]
Meaning: firstly, philosophers of language prioritise their inquiry on the nature of meaning. They seek to explain what it means to “mean” something. Topics in that vein include the nature of synonymy, the origins of meaning itself, and how any meaning can ever really be known. Another project under this heading of special interest to analytic philosophers of language is the investigation into the manner in which sentences are composed into a meaningful whole out of the meaning of its parts. This idea theories of meaning, most commonly associated with the British empiricist tradition of Locke, Berkeley, Hume. They claim that meanings are purely mental contents provoked by signs.[30] Although this view of meaning has been beset by a number of problems from the beginning interest in it has been renewed by some contemporary theorists under the guise of semantic internalism.[31]
In semantic internalism there is what is called truth-conditional theories. These theories hold meaning to be the conditions under which an expression may be true or false.[32] This tradition goes back at least to Frege and is associated with a rich body of modern work, spearheaded by philosophers like Alfred Tarski and Donald Davidson.[33] For Davidson, the most basic is that we are finite beings whose mastery of the indefinitely many expressions of our language must somehow arise out of our mastery of finite resources. Otherwise, there would be an unbounded number of distinct things to learn in learning a language, which would make language learning impossible for finite beings like ourselves. The linguistic competence of a finite being of our sort must be the result of the interaction of a finite number of basic competencies.[34]
This point led Davidson to emphasize what he called a finite primitives constraint, namely, that there cannot be an unbounded number of primitive meanings of expressions in our language. Davidson argued that this constraint was incompatible with certain proposals of the time. It ruled out Israel Scheffler’s proposal that intentional verb phrases be treated as primitive unstructured units.[35] In Scheffler’s view, the verb phrase, believes that Socrates was a philosopher, was to be treated as a primitive unstructured predicate—believes-that-Socrates-was-a-philosopher. Since this proposal would entail infinitely many primitive expressions, it violated the finite primitives constraint.[36]
Davidson argued in addition that the finite primitives constraint ruled out certain versions of Frege’s proposal that words used in intentional contexts do not have their ordinary senses but instead have a special oblique sense, and have different still doubly oblique senses in doubly intentional contexts, and so on for deeper intentional contexts. Frege’s whole philosophy of language – and that of much philosophy of language in the analytic tradition – is shaped by the conception of validity which is implicit in his system.[37]
 The basis of Frege’s mature account of language is his theory of Bedeutung. There are two striking things about this. First, he takes Bedeutung to account for what matters about meaning for the purposes of logic, and perhaps for science in general. And, secondly, he understands Bedeutung in a way which the German word makes natural, but would seem odd to us if we took it to be simply equivalent to ‘meaning’. The German word is sometimes used to speak of meaning a thing by a word, or even of the thing meant by a word. In his account of the Bedeutung of expressions, Frege seems to follow this suggestion, and to look for a kind of thing which might be assigned to a word as its Bedeutung.[38]
In this sort of view, philosopher has its ordinary sense in Socrates was a philosopher, an oblique sense in Mary thinks that Socrates was a philosopher, a doubly oblique sense in Jack says that Mary thinks that Socrates was a philosopher, etc. If an oblique sense of an expression is not determined by the regular sense of the expression, and similarly for the doubly oblique and higher order senses, then this view appears to be committed to indefinitely many primitive senses, which violates Davidson’s finite primitives constraint. These and other similar early arguments of Davidson had a major impact at the time and it is now widely agreed that any acceptable analysis in these areas must respect some version or other of the finite primitives constraint.[39]
            Given that there is no bound to the number of expressions in a language, the finite primitives constraint implies that most expressions in the language are not primitive. Non-primitive expressions are themselves composed of primitive expressions and it seems that their meanings must somehow be determined by the expressions out of which they are composed, the meanings of those expressions, and the way they are put together. Davidson’s positive proposal was that an explanation of how the meanings of complex expressions in a language depend on the meanings of their parts could be achieved though a theory of truth for the whole language or at least for a fragment containing the relevant expressions. The theory was to be modeled on Tarski’s theory of truth for a certain formal language L. It was to satisfy a version of Tarski’s Convention T, allowing proofs of relevant T sentences of the form, x is true in L iff p, where x was to be replaced by something that referred to a sentence of the language and p was to be replaced by that sentence or a translation of that sentence.[40]
Language use: philosophers of language seek to better understand what speakers and listeners do with language in communication, and how it is used socially. Specific interests may include the topics of language learning, language creation, and speech acts. This theory of language use, for example theories by the later Wittgenstein, helped inaugurate the idea of “meaning as use”, and a communitarian view of language. Wittgenstein was interested in the way in the which the communities use language, and how far it can be taken.[41] Wittgenstein rejected many of the assumptions of the Tractatus, arguing that the meaning of words is best as their within a given language-game.[42]
Language cognition: philosophers like to know how language relates to the minds of both the speaker and the interpreter. This specific interest is the grounds for successful translation of words into other words. Through logical analysis, Wittgenstein held that we could arrive at a conception of language as consisting of elementary propositions related by the now-familiar elements of first-order logic. Any sentence with a sense could have that sense perspicuously rendered in such a system, and any sentence that did not yield to such analysis would not have a sense at all. "Everything that can be thought at all can be thought clearly. Everything that can be said can be said clearly."[43]
The relationship between language and reality: philosophers of language investigate how language and meaning relate to truth and the world. They tend to be less concerned with which sentences are actually true, and more with what kinds meanings can be true or false. A truth oriented philosopher of language might wonder whether or not a meaningless sentence can be true or false, or whether or not sentences can express propositions about things that do not exist, rather than the way sentences are used.
To be a realist about the subject matters of these discourses is to think that our thought about them aspires to reflect an objective reality, and sometimes succeeds in this aim. Thus, when I judge that there are three chairs in the room, I express a belief which aims to reflect an objective fact; and beliefs such as this often do succeed in reflecting the objective facts of the matter, so that the judgement in question is true. Likewise in the case of moral discourse: when I judge that killing is wrong, I am expressing a belief which aims to reflect an objective fact and which is successful in this aim.[44]
For example, if I say that if it is raining, the streets will be wet, I am not thereby accepting that it is actually raining.) The question for the non-cognitivist is therefore this: what is the semantic function of the occurrence of “Murder is wrong” in the antecedent of the above conditional? Since I am not there expressing disapproval of murder, the account of its semantic function must be different from that given for the straightforward assertion that murder is wrong. But now we are going to have a problem in accounting for the following apparently valid inference:
(1) Murder is wrong.
(2) If murder is wrong, then getting your little brother to murder people is wrong.
Therefore:
(3) Getting your little brother to murder people is wrong.[45]
If the semantic function of “murder is wrong” as it appears in (1) is different from its semantic function as it appears in (2), isn’t someone arguing in this way simply guilty of equivocation? In order for the argument to be valid, the occurrence of “murder is wrong” in (1) has to mean the same thing as the occurrence of “murder is wrong” in (2). But if “murder is wrong” has a different semantic function in (1) and (2), then it certainly doesn’t mean the same thing in (1) and (2). So the above argument is apparently no more valid than:
(1) My beer has a head on it.
(2) If something has a head on it, then it must have eyes and ears.
Therefore:
(3) My beer must have eyes and ears.
This argument is obviously invalid, because it relies on an equivocation on two senses of “head”, in (1) and (2) respectively.[46]
Problem: it cannot be said that, philosophy of language is restricted to conceptual analysis, to clarifying the basic concepts dealing with language. In some the tasks philosophers of language involve themselves are classification of linguistic acts, of “uses” or “functions” of language, of types of vagueness, of types of terms of various sorts of metaphor.[47] Language has a problem a word can mean several thing in different context. For instance, the word grasp, in a sentence like; I grasp what you saying”. Because in this sense grasp could mean possessing something with hand but statement is an object to be possessed. So in essence, to talk all about things which are not perce3ived by the senses, we are forced to use language metaphorically.[48]
Similarities
            There is a common ground on how to communicate properly without vagueness. This proper communication of language must be base on good construction. And to see how this language depicts reality, for example, every newspaper reporter went to a local bar to hear the news. Stanley argues that, the statement above contains a covert location variable that is semantically and hence syntactically bound on the natural reading of, and that is a fortiori present as a syntactically articulated element of the sentence.[49] Stanley also suggests that covert pronouns associated with expressions such as ‘local’ are responsible for weak crossover effects, restrictions on binding easily observed in sentences containing overt pronouns. For instance, one cannot hear a reading of, on which the overt pronoun ‘her’ is bound by the lower quantifier ‘every reporter’: Heri local bar sponsored every reporter. Stanley argues that one can see the same effect in viz. the absence of a reading that says that every reporter was sponsored by a bar local to that reporter: A local bar sponsored every reporter. In other words, the same syntactic constraints on binding seem responsible for the absence of the intended bound readings of statements above.[50] In this aspect linguistics, linguistic philosophy and philosophy of language are interconnected.
Differences
             The major difference is that, their emphasis and what they intend to solve are quite different. Philosophy of language emphasis more on meaning of a word and to see whether this word is truth when use, while, linguistics emphasis more on structure of a statement and how it is pronounced. Linguistic philosophy in its own enterprise engaged in how linguistics term can have a reference in the world, to see if any way linguistic concept can be empirically verifiable.
Conclusion
            Having considered the nature and issues of philosophy of language, linguistic and linguistic philosophy, we are able to understand that, in doing philosophy well one need language and how to use it. Language helps us to shape our idea and to be refined in our expression. In which linguistic really helps to have a good knowledge on how to construction of our statement in order to suit the idea we intend to communicate at the same time to know the etymology of each word. A philosopher cannot philosophise well without a good grasp of language because language is the tool of philosophy.
            Knowing a language and how to use it well is quite different from whether what we are saying using language can be comprehend by the audience through references to the reality out there. On this ground, the linguistic philosophy helps to understand that, it is not just saying so many thing but we should to understand that, whether what we are saying can be found in the world of experience because human being learn fast through experience referring to concrete thing in the world. So in this enterprise every philosophical utterance should point to something in the world.
            Gazing at what is done above, clarification of concept of linguistic, philosophy of language and linguistic philosophy and their enterprise we are to discover that, the three enterprises are interdependence or interwoven. One cannot stand without others, and because of this complementary we then say philosophy use linguistic concept to express the ideas in the mind as well concrete thing that is contain in reality.



Bibliography
Akmajian , Adrian et al. Linguistic. 6th edition. New York: MIT Press, 2010.

Alston, William P. Philosophy of Language. U.S.A: Prentice-Hall, Inc., 1964.

Block, Ned. “Conceptual Role Semantics” in the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

Carr, Philip. English Phonetics and Phonology: An Introduction. Germany: Blackwell Publishing, 2003

Carnap, Rudolf. The Logical Structure of the World (Die Logische Aufbau der Welt), translated by George, E. New York: Open Court Classics, 1999.
Chierchia, Gennaro and McConnell-Ginet Sally. Meaning and Grammar: An Introduction to Semantics. Massachusetts: Cambridge MIT Press, 2000.

Chomsky, Noam. Syntactic Structures. London: Oxford University Press,2002.

______________. Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1965.

Davidson, Donald. Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation. London: Oxford University Press, 2001.

____________. Meaning, Truth, Language, and Reality. London: Oxford University Press, 2005.

de Saussure, Ferdinand. Course in General Linguistics. 3rd edition, translated by R. Harris Chicago: Open Court Publishing Company, 1986.

Frege, Gottlob. "On Sense and Reference" in The Frege Reader, edited by M. Beaney. London: Penguin Press, 1997.
Halliday, Michael A. K. On Language and Linguistics. New York: Continuum International Publishing Group, 2006.

Harman, Gilbert. Davidson’s Contribution to the Philosophy of Language. New York: Princeton University Press, July 6, 2009.


Jakobson, Roman. six lectures on Sound and Meaning. New York: Cambridge MIT Press, 1937.

Lass, Roger. Phonology: An Introduction to Basic Concepts. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998.

Lewis, C. S. The Joyful Christian. New York: Macmillan Publishing Company, 1977.

“Linguistic Philosophy”Define Linguistic Philosophy at dictionary.reference. com

Locke, John. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding edited by P. Nidditch. New York: Oxford University Press, 1975.

Martinet, Andre. Elements of General linguistic, translated by Elizabeth Palmer Rubbert, Vol.1. London: Faber Publisher, 1960.

Mill, J.S. System of Logic: Ratiocinative and Inductive. Stockton: Cambridge University Press of the Pacific, 2002.

Miller,  Alexander. Philosophy of Language, 2nd edition. London: Routledge, 2007.

Morris, Michael. An Introduction to the Philosophy of Language.  New York: Cambridge University Press, 2007.

Monk, Ray. How to Read Wittgenstein. New York: W.W. Norton &Company, 2005.

Mougeon, Raymond and Terry Nadasdi, Sociolinguistics Discontinuity in Minority Language Communities. Chicago: Linguistic Society of America, 1998.

Mukherjee, Joybrato. “Stylistic” Encyclopedia of Linguistics, chapter 49

Pagin, P. “Are Holism and Compositionality Compatible?” in Olismo. edited by Massimo dell’Utri. Macerata: Quodlibet, 2002.

Panini, The Ashtadhyayi, translated by Vasu S. C. Vol. 2. India: Vedic Books Publisher, 1996.

“Panini (Indian Grammarian)”, Encyclopedia Britannica, www.britannica.com 24 January, 2014.

Penco, C. “Filosofia del Linguaggio” in Enciclopedia Garzantina della Filosofia, edited by Gianni Vattimo (Milian: Garzanti Editori, 2004), p. 23

Rorty, Richard. Introduction: Meta-philosophical Difficulties of Linguistic Philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1967.

Russell, Bertrand. "Descriptions" in Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy. London: George Allen and Unqin Ltd. 1919.

Scheffler, Israel. “An Inscriptional Approach to Indirect Discourse,” Analysis. New York: Rouledge Publishing Company, 1954.

Stainton, Robert J. Philosophical Perspectives on Language. Peterborough: Broadview Press, 2001.

Stanley, Jason. “Context and Logical Form” in Journal Linguistics and Philosophy, Vol. 23, no. 4, (2000), pp.391–434

Stanley, Jason & Timothy Williamson, “Knowing How” Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 98, no. 8, (2001), pp.411–444

Sellars, Wilfrid. Science and Metaphysics. Atascasdero: Ridgeview Press, 1967.

Tarski, Alfred. The Semantical Conception of Truth. London: Oxford University Press, 1944.

Wolf, Michael. "Rigid Designation and Anaphoric Theories of Reference" in Journal Philosophical Studies Vol. 130, no. 2, (2006), pp. 351-375

Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Philosophical Investigations, 3rd edition, translated by G. E. M. Anscombe. New York: MacMillan Publishing Co., 1958.

______________. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, translated by C. Ogden. New York: Dover Publisher, 1999.





[1] John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding edited by P. Nidditch (New York: Oxford University Press, 1975), BK. III, Ch. I
[2] Michael A. K. Halliday, On Language and Linguistics (New York: Continuum International Publishing Group, 2006), p. 7
[3] Andre Martinet, Elements of General linguistic,  translated by Elizabeth Palmer Rubbert, Vol.1 (London: Faber Publisher, 1960), p. 15
[4] Panini, The Ashtadhyayi, translated by Vasu S. C, Vol. 2 (India: Vedic Books Publisher, 1996), p. 25
[5] “Panini (Indian Grammarian)”, Encyclopedia Britannica, www.britannica.com (24 January,2014)
[6] Roman Jakobson, six lectures on Sound and Meaning (New York: Cambridge MIT Press, 1937), p. 20
[7] Gennaro Chierchia and McConnell-Ginet Sally, Meaning and Grammar: An Introduction to Semantics (Massachusetts: Cambridge MIT Press, 2000), p. 5
[8] Adrian Akmajian , et al, Linguistic, 6th edition (New York: MIT Press, 2010), p. 50
[9] Roger Lass, Phonology: An Introduction to Basic Concepts (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998), p. 1
[10] Philip Carr, English Phonetics and Phonology: An Introduction (Germany: Blackwell Publishing, 2003), p. 5
[11] Robert J. Stainton, Philosophical Perspectives on Language (Peterborough: Broadview Press), p. 10
[12] http://www.sil.org/linguistics
[13] Noam Chomsky, Syntactic Structures (London: Oxford University Press,2002), p. 11
[14] P. Pagin, “Are Holism and Compositionality Compatible?” in Olismo, edited by Massimo dell’Utri (Macerata: Quodlibet, 2002), p. 12
[15] Ferdinand de Saussure, Course in General Linguistics, 3rd edition, translated by R. Harris (Chicago: Open Court Publishing Company, 1986), pp. 9-10, 15
[16] Noam Chomsky, Aspects of the Theory of Syntax (Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1965), p. 12
[17] Raymond Mougeon and Terry Nadasdi, Sociolinguistics Discontinuity in Minority Language Communities (Chicago: Linguistic Society of America, 1998), pp. 40-55
[18] Joybrato Mukherjee, “Stylistic” Encyclopedia of Linguistics, chapter 49
[19] Richard Rorty, Introduction: Meta-philosophical Difficulties of Linguistic Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1967), p. 3
[20] Wilfrid Sellars, Science and Metaphysics (Atascasdero: Ridgeview Press, 1967), p. 5
[21] J.S. Mill, System of Logic: Ratiocinative and Inductive (Stockton: Cambridge University Press of the Pacific, 2002), Arts. 1-2, Sec. 5
[22] J.S. Mill, System of Logic: Ratiocinative and Inductive,
[23] John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding edited by P. Nidditch
[24]G. Frege, "On Sense and Reference" in The Frege Reader, edited by M. Beaney (London: Penguin Press, 1997), p. 153
[25] Michael Wolf, "Rigid Designation and Anaphoric Theories of Reference" in Journal Philosophical Studies Vol. 130, no. 2, (2006), pp. 351-375
[26] Rudolf Carnap, The Logical Structure of the World (Die Logische Aufbau der Welt), translated by George, E. (New York: Open Court Classics, 1999), p. 30
[27] G. Frege, "On Sense and Reference" in The Frege Reader, edited by M. Beaney
[28] Bertrand Russell, "Descriptions" in Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy (London: George Allen and Unqin Ltd. 1919), pp. 167-180
[29] “Linguistic Philosophy”Define Linguistic Philosophy at dictionary.reference. com
[30]C. Penco, “Filosofia del Linguaggio” in Enciclopedia Garzantina della Filosofia, edited by Gianni Vattimo (Milian: Garzanti Editori, 2004), p. 23
[31] Ned Block “Conceptual Role Semantics” in the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
[32] Donald Davidson, Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation (London: Oxford University Press, 2001), p. 26
[33] Alfred Tarski, The Semantical Conception of Truth (London: Oxford University Press, 1944), p. 5
[34] Donald Davidson, Meaning, Truth, Language, and Reality (London: Oxford University Press, 2005), p. 5
[35] Israel Scheffler, “An Inscriptional Approach to Indirect Discourse,” Analysis, (New York: Rouledge Publishing Company, 1954), pp. 83-90
[36] Gilbert Harman, Davidson’s Contribution to the Philosophy of Language (New York: Princeton University Press, July 6, 2009), pp. 1-2
[37] Michael Morris, An Introduction to the Philosophy of Language ( New York: Cambridge University Press, 2007), p. 28
[38] Michael Morris, An Introduction to the Philosophy of Language, p. 29
[39] Gilbert Harman, Davidson’s Contribution to the Philosophy of Language, pp. 2-3
[40] Gilbert Harman, Davidson’s Contribution to the Philosophy of Language, pp. 3-4
[41] Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, 3rd edition, translated by G. E. M. Anscombe (New York: MacMillan Publishing Co., 1958), p. 50
[42] Ray Monk, How to Read Wittgenstein (New York: W.W. Norton &Company, 2005), p.5
[43]Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, translated by C. Ogden (New York: Dover Publisher, 1999), p. 116
[44] Alexander Miller, Philosophy of Language, 2nd edition, (London: Routledge, 2007), p. 309
[45] Alexander Miller, Philosophy of Language, 2nd edition,
[46] Alexander Miller, Philosophy of Language, 2nd edition,
[47] William P. Alston, Philosophy of Language (U.S.A: Prentice-Hall, Inc., 1964), p. 8
[48] C. S. Lewis, The Joyful Christian (New York: Macmillan Publishing Company, 1977), p. 109
[49] Jason Stanley, “Context and Logical Form” in Journal Linguistics and Philosophy, Vol. 23, no. 4, (2000), pp.391–434
[50] Jason Stanley & Timothy Williamson, “Knowing How” Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 98, no. 8, (2001), pp.411–444

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

SUMMARY OF PROVIDENTISSIMUS DEUS, ENCYCLICAL LETTER OF POPE LEO XIII ON THE STUDY OF THE HOLY SCRIPTURE.

summary and appraisal of chapters one, two and three of the book The African Origin of Greek Philosophy: An Exercise in Afrocentrism, by Innocent C. Onyewuenyi.

THE LAST THREE WAYS TO PROVES GOD'S EXISTENCE BY THOMAS AQUINAS