PHILOSOPHY OF THE SOCIAL SCIENCES


v    7/3/2011

F    Course Outline

1.                  What is philosophy of the social sciences?
2.                  Issues in the philosophy of sciences
3.                  On Induction
I.Hume
II.Kant
III.Popper
4.                  Mill on the systematization of the social sciences
5.                  The human sciences and critical theory
6.                  On culture and the human person
7.                  Philosophy and technology
8.                  Rorty and solidarity

F    Introduction
The most important question that philosophers of the social sciences want to resolve is the issue of whether scientism is true. But what is scientism? Scientism is the view that humanity and indeed social sciences should ape or imitate natural sciences. The pertinent question here is: Is scientism true? The answer to this question will be arrived at by examining the nature and the theoretical constructs of the social sciences and for this, J. S. Mill would be discoursed and also the issue of induction as viewed by Hume, Kant and Popper.
The natural scientists believed that natural sciences should not be neglected as the major way of acquiring knowledge. Now, would this be true without the introduction of some aspects of the social sciences as a way of acquiring knowledge?
v    14/3/ 2011

The field of science or technology provides a veritable toll for linking philosophy and technology together. However, students of philosophy often fail to link philosophy and the social sciences and one of the ways of doing this is by answering the question: what is philosophy?

It is not only knowing what philosophy is, but understanding philosophy and linking it with other disciplines like the social sciences. This will in a way help us to understand the philosophical underpinning of other disciplines like the social sciences, technology and so forth.

F    What is philosophy?
Philosophy simply is the study of the fundamental ideas of life and existence. But what is studying? Studying in this sense does not mean the same as ideas contained in the discourse. Studying implies that one inquires into something. Through study, we learn the basics of the subject-matter of a particular discourse and then we make out impute. Studying therefore implies learning, thinking, asking questions and criticizing of ideas. Not many will agree with this definition because philosophers do not agree as to a univocal definition of philosophy. The above definition is therefore tentative. Any attempt however, to defining philosophy is expected to include its critical element. Consequently, the original encyclopedia of philosophy has it that philosophy of a critical discussion of all critical discussions. In this light, philosophy is seen as a critical enterprise.
According to H. S. Stainland, philosophy is the criticism of the ideas we live by. In trying to understand the world, human beings form ideas and beliefs and these ideas and beliefs have consequences. Most countries in the world for instance, believe in democracy and the consequences of democracy are democratization. Because we sometimes hold false ideas and beliefs, we need to examine and criticize them in other to either endorse or refute them with good arguments. Criticism therefore is the hallmark of philosophical enterprise.
Philosophical enterprise at all times is about criticisms. As such philosophy should be an analytical endeavourer. Let us take for instance the fact that Plato held that there is a world of Form and ideas. We should inquire why Plato had such a belief in the first instance. What are his reasons? Is Plato right in holding this belief? Is the theory of the world of Form and Ideas true and to what extent? By doing this, one engages in a philosophical analysis.
According to Professor Olusegun Oladipo, philosophy is a puzzle-solving activity. This definition presupposes some level of uncertainties and worries in life. As such, we need to come to terms with these uncertainties and worries if we hope to make a meaning out of life’s experiences. Coming to term with these uncertainties and worries on the other hand, presupposes making choices between alternatives and philosophy helps us to make these choices between alternatives. This implies accepting or rejecting one alternative choice against another, accepting or rejection one idea or belief against another. In this light, philosophy can be seen as a rejection or acceptance of an idea or belief against another.
This explains why Socrates defined philosophy as a preparation for death. Why did Socrates say this? This is because one of the most striking thing philosophers have always faced is the issue of death. Without the fear of death, people would probably not do philosophy. It is the fear of death that makes people to lead a good life. In trying to lead the good life, we face different choices; and to make the right choice, we need to criticize the choices we make.
According to Bertrand Russell, philosophy is an attempt to understand the hierarchy of beings. Philosophy as such is a systematic discipline to avoid chaos.


v    21/3/2011

F    The Nature of Philosophical Inquiry
There are close affinity between philosophy and theology, between philosophy and science. Like theology, philosophy seeks for interpretation, meaning and understanding about things in reality that are as yet undiscovered and unexplained. Theology seeks to understand things about the world and philosophy joins theology to do the same. The only difference is that philosophy does not reach a final conclusion its search about things that are yet unknown. Theology on the other hand arrives a final conclusion which is dogmatic in nature.
But again like science, philosophy uses human reason to interrogate facts, what we know unlike theology which deals with things unknown. Theology has a final answer which Russell calls ‘dogmatic answers’. Like theology, science provides definite knowledge but that of theology is based on faith. Unlike theology, philosophy provides no final answers or definite knowledge in the areas of fact.
Philosophy seeks answer to fundamental problems of human existence such as: ‘What is the relationship between mind and nature? What is the scope of human knowledge? What is the nature of reality? How can we distinguish between appearance and reality? What does it mean to live a good life? These are and many others are the questions that preoccupy the mind of philosophers and they are contested questions. Philosophy unlike science is a restless and indefinite quest for knowledge. Science provides a definite answer to their findings whereas philosophy provides no definite answer. Philosophy asks relentless questions and as such is an open system because it does not arrive at a definite position. Philosophy therefore stands apart from other disciplines.
v    What is the nature of philosophical inquiry?
Form what has been said thus far, it is evident that philosophical inquiry is a fundamental one, meaning that they are very important and unavoidable. Put differently, questions raised by philosophers are fundamental questions. Philosophical questions or problems transcend assumptions. Philosophical puzzle begins where others have stopped. Philosophical questions raise fundamental questions anew. In philosophy therefore, we raise questions that are at the root of other discipline. Philosophical questions are unavoidable such that any attempt to avoid them poses danger to the society at large.
·                     What is distinctive about in philosophical inquiry is that it provides “guide” to issues. Some scholars have argued that philosophy does not have any relevance given the level of scientific and technological advancement that we have attained. At best, they opined that philosophy should become part of psychology – naturalized theory of V. O. Quine. The fact remains however that if philosophy is discarded as a discipline, then we would have to face greater challenges about human existence such as Nuclear weapons, wars, election malpractices as we do experience in Nigeria, etc. The truth remains that in dealing with such problems as the ones just mentioned one need to ask the fundamental questions which by their very nature is philosophical. Philosophy and indeed philosophizing is therefore indispensable.  

·                     To this extent, philosophical problems have a general character. Meaning by that, that it affects people of all cultures, epochs and civilization. Philosophers aim at generating general answers that are universal. Philosophy produces evergreen theories that stand the test of time. This is because philosophical puzzles are abstract in nature.

·                     Philosophical puzzle/inquiry is “perennial” in nature – they live with us.

·                     Philosophical question arise from ontological wonder and this could be seen from the perspective of the ancient philosophers like Plato, Aristotle, Socrates, Parmenides etc, who themselves believes that philosophy arises from wonder and curiosity. A philosopher will always wonder at the happenings in the world. Philosophical inquiry is a detached form of inquiry. The philosopher removes or detaches himself emotionally from his investigations. Philosophical inquiries are therefore from all forms of emotional attachments.

·                     Another point is that philosophy inquiry has its own ‘constituency’. Philosophers always have their own constituency just as J.S.Mill wrote on the subjection of women.

·                     Philosophy is about saying the unsayable. This explains why we talk about the nature of God, the issue of death and human existence.

v    Article for Review: What is philosophy? By A.S Staniland

F    Tools of Philosophical Analysis.

Philosophy is a rational inquiry that involves critical reasoning. Philosophers aim at clarifying concepts to eliminate ambiguity; they give good reasons why an idea may be rejected. To interrogate reality then, philosophy depends on certain tools such as:

·                     Clarification of concepts
·                     The evaluation of beliefs

v    28/3/2011
Every human society and individual persons operate or are guided by beliefs, views and convictions about the world and the people and events around them. In most cases, these beliefs, views and convictions are held uncritical; in other words, societies and individuals often operate in most cases without caring to criticize these beliefs, views and conviction so as to find out why they hold such beliefs and views. The task of philosophers in this regard is to help the society and the individual persons to evaluate these held beliefs and convictions for the betterment or reconstruction of the society and the individual human person. If society and the individual continually evaluate their beliefs, then they stand the chance of taking better decisions about their beliefs. We have taken critical evaluation of beliefs as a tool for philosophical analysis because we often take our beliefs for granted. Our beliefs and world-views are often assumptions. Philosophy helps us to criticize and organize these beliefs and assumptions in other to reconstruct them. Our lives become worth living when we examine and re-examine the beliefs we live-by and this is what philosophy helps us to achieve. Our examination of the beliefs we live-by helps us to recognize how these beliefs affect our relationship with other people and our reaction to the world in general.
Another important tool of philosophical analysis is the clarification of concepts or beliefs. Basic or fundamental concepts need to be clarified so as to avoid ambiguity. Clarification of concepts can be done in two ways:
1.                  Historical clarification, and
2.                  Theoretical clarification
In the historical context, the concept we may wish to clarify may have a historical origin. We cannot do otherwise therefore other than to employ a historical approach to such a clarification. Take as example such concepts as Nazism, Democracy, and rule of law. To clarify Nazism would necessarily require that we go back to history so as to discover the origin of such concept.
 Other concepts with a general character such as love, constitution, mercy, politics, law, justice and so forth does not lend itself to an easy clarification and we cannot find any historical origins for such concepts. Consequently, philosophers often revert to theoretical analysis when they try to define such concepts. Appeal to authority is another way of clarifying such concepts as these. Often you hear such comments as “according to so and so.”
v    Philosophy is a normative discipline which deals with values, with what ought to be rather than with what is. Science on the other hand, deals with what is, with facts.

v    4/4/2011

F    Understanding the Philosophy of Science.
The scientific enterprise concerns the modern period upwards. Philosophers were interested in the happenings in the field of science because scientific progress attracted their attention. The systematic nature, organized, progressive and recognizable body of knowledge of science made the scientific method very important and attracted the attention of philosophers. David Hums and Immanuel Kant developed interest in science because of the indelible fact about the scientific enterprise. The scientific enterprise is also said to be universal. Scientific ruminations have been there before the emergence of Newton and Galileo in the modern era in the history of philosophy. Aristotle talked more of science so was Plato as well but it became more pronounced during the modern era of which Isaac Newton and Galileo were of important figures.
·                     Scientific Experiment
There are principles behind experimentation and this is induction. The principle of induction simply put states that the future will resemble the past. In other words, the principle of induction affirms uniformity/regularity in nature. Also, the principle of causality states that to every effect, there must be a cause. As such, induction/causation is at the root of every philosophical inquiry in philosophy of science.
The principle of induction says it all; following Hume’s position that to prove the principle of induction, you first have to assume that the principle of causality is true, which also follows that the principle of causality rests on the uniformity of nature. Consequently the principle of induction has a solid foundation within the scientific enterprise.
F    Logical Positivism on the Method of Science
Facts about science said earlier were later articulated by the logical positivist. They tried to do two major things:
1.                  Demarcation of science from non-science
2.                  Make science the hallmark of knowledge.
They meant to say that science is rational, objective, value neutral inquiry, etc. The logical positivists were in love with experimentation which helps is to judge or conclude which theory to enclose at a particular time.
According to the logical positivist, science is:
a.                   A value neutral inquiry
b.                  Objective
c.                   Rational
Logical positivist in their rumination intended
d.                  To build science on a firm/strong foundation
e.                   To demarcate science from noon-science/pseudo science.
 

F    Observation:

Notice that nothing can be said of the philosophy of science without getting to the root of induction. The principle of induction is the underlying principle behind experimentation. This is because the scientific enterprise will often come out to be the same following the fact that the property of “A”, which is placed under experiment ensures in such  way that it is capable of producing the same result over and over again.

v    11/04/2011

F    Popper and Kuhn: Critical component of Inductivism
The inductivists assume that we can move from the observed behaviour of a thing to the unobserved. In other words, the inductivists move from what is true of a set of observed facts to another set of facts of the same kind in the future. This implies that a property of observed fact will remain true even when it is not observed. Thus if I touch water today and it produces a cooling effect, it also follows that if I touch water tomorrow, it will still produce the same cooling effect. This position ignores the fact that there could be such a thing as global warming as we have it these days which is capable of causing the water to produce warm or hot effect instead of cooling effect.
·                     Hume?
In his critique of induction, Hume poses the question: “Are we rationally justified to move from the instances of observed facts to instances yet to be observed? According to Hume, the answer to this is NO. Hume’s position is based on epistemological argument.  What then, is Hume’s logical or epistemological critique of induction? Hume made a distinction between matters of fact (Science; epiricism) and relations of ideas (Philosophy); that is distinction between logical and psychological alms of induction.
According to Hume, a statement is either analytic (synthetic a prior) or it makes a claim from what can be observed (matter of fact).
·                     Hume: matter of fact equals knowledge
·                     Relations of ideas equal no knowledge.

Hume went even further to assert that matters of facts cannot be conclusively verified leading Hume thereby to skepticism. Hume is therefore both an empiricist and at the same time a skeptics. Hume’s position when followed to its logical conclusion, leads to the end of philosophy and this is what Immanuel Kant labored to resuscitate by first of all refuting Hume. Hume called for an end to philosophy. This is because according to him, science relates to matters of fact while philosophy relates to relations of ideas.

Hume dismantled both matters of fact and relations of ideas. According to him, there is always a possibility of error concerning our knowledge claim through sense experience (Science). Furthermore, Hume considers relations of ideas (Philosophy) as trivial. This implied that both science and philosophy were dismantled by Hume. Unfortunately however, Hume did not proffer any solution he thus created; instead, he left us with nothing. In the final analysis, Hume assumes that induction is inescapable because nature is too strong for principles. Human nature says that induction is true.
F    Popper critique of Hume.
According to Popper, Hume made a fundamental error in assuming that knowledge is something that remains true at all times once it is proven to be true. In other words, Hume assumed that our knowledge claims once proven to be true, will remain true always. In other words, knowledge is something eternal, such that once we know it, we know it. This assumption explains Hume’s position concerning uniformity of nature. But it is conceivable that such knowledge may not be true tomorrow.
According to Popper, knowledge is not something that can be conclusively verified by experience and that remains true at all times; because the human capacity to know is fallible. Popper holds that you don’t go out there to observe and propound theories based on observation; instead human reason formulates theories and then goes out there in the field to confirm or refute these theories. For Popper, Hume was right in holding that induction is not true based on rational thinking(Logical arm) but that Hume was wrong in holding that induction is true based on human psychological disposition of constant association of events (Psychological arm).
·                     Trial and error elimination
For Popper, neither human beings nor animals live by induction. He opines that our lives are guided more by trial and error elimination principle. According to him, human beings have so many beliefs, customs and ideologies that guide and shape their lives. These beliefs, customs and ideologies or principles are accepted in the first instance because they work in a particular instance. However, as soon as they fail work in a different instance of situation, these accepted beliefs; customs and ideologies are shut down or discarded in favour of new once. This implies what Popper called Testability theory.
According to him, it is in testing our beliefs, customs and ideologies – which implies the introduction of criticism, that we discover a theory that works or does not. This then is the foundation of testability or falsification as a criterion of demarcation. Science is to be separated from non-science or pseudo-science because it is assumed that only science is capable of providing authentic knowledge. Scientific progress in acquiring authentic knowledge necessitated the logical positivists insistent that philosophy should ape or imitate scientific method.

v    Hand Out

F    What are the social sciences?
According to Otite (1979), the social sciences are concerned with the scientific study of man in society. Specifically, the social sciences deal with human interactions and with the relationships between people. Notably, other subject areas deal with one aspect or the other of the society, but the term social sciences normally refers to Anthropology, Economics, Political Science, Social Psychology and Sociology. In some Universities, Geography, History, law and statistics are also taught in the faculty of the social science.
The question is: What is it that makes these subject areas social scientific? What do they have in common? As academic disciplines, they deal with man in his social and cultural context. As separate discipline, each has its own historical evolution, perspectives and interest, as well as its own emphasis in research methods and techniques. But, the social sciences have a meeting point, a common ground for their operations on man and the society.
As a result, the social sciences make use of common concepts like “role:, “status” ‘system’ etc. This goes to show that although each social science discipline is distinctive on its own, they maintain a flexibility across their boundaries. The interrelatedness of the social science gives room for their connection or overlap with other disciplines such as Biology, Anatomy and Neurology. For example, there is a convergence of interest by social and natural scientists in studying and solving problems of malnutrition and its effects on intelligence and learning. To be sure, the problems the social scientists attempt to resolve are immanent and important and as such social theories could have direct impact and meaning in real life situations.
The “behavioural sciences” contributes an emergent subject area from the social sciences. They ape (imitate) the method and rules of the social science. The behavioural sciences emerged from a Ford Foundation Programme and later became current in the U.S.A. in the 1950s.
The distinctive nature of the social sciences is therefore the attempt to substantiate social phenomena through empirical facts and investigations. The founding fathers of sociology, for example Durkheim emphasized the need for providing common grounds for wider comparisons and generalizations about social reality. This emphasis would help in testing interaction and validation or modification of theory and observed phenomena and facts. To this end, the social sciences attempts to, and indeed rely on scientific methods in studying man from various perspectives. This is done so as to ensure a comprehensive analysis of human behaviour. The common methods of the social sciences include use of survey, questionnaires, refined systematic interview methods, prolonged participant observation, vigorous statistical methods and testing, and systematic analysis. Social scientists use these methods to provide objective works which provide possibilities and opportunities for prediction leading to conclusions on recognizable patterns of group institutional behaviour.
The effort to understand human behaviour and its implication for social conduct is ultimately geared towards finding solutions to teething human problems in the areas of institutional structure and organization. Solutions are also sought for personal, political, religious and other kinds of social problems. In analyzing the processes of decisions and choice among human members of the organized social structure, the social sciences and their theories become crucial for social policy.
F    Facts, Concepts, Theories and Science in the Social Sciences
The main concern of science and by extension the social sciences are to understand the world in which our experiences emanate and are defined. In order to understand h world, scientists use concepts and relate theories to facts. A theory is a system of ideas held to explain groups of facts or phenomena. A fact is a datum of experience which verified can be used as basic of reference. A concept is a general notion, or an idea of a class of objects or phenomena.
F    Philosophy of the social sciences

The philosophy of the social sciences includes discussions of methodological, epistemological and logical issues in psychology, sociology, anthropology, history and related domains. Philosophical engagements in the arena of the social sciences are suggestive of certain core divergences between the social sciences and the natural sciences. The questions that arise as philosophy investigates the social sciences include but are not limited to:

·                     Can we say that human social life as well as individual experiences which the social sciences claim to study are or are not similar to the non sentient beings and factors studied in the natural sciences?

·                      Put differently, are human experiences and social experiences explainable by scientific processes? Can we, in short, describe human social life using the scientific method?

·                     Is it the case that the social sciences are the same as the natural sciences in terms of the subject matter they study, the method they use and the effectiveness of their result?

·                      Can we identify a distinctive method for social research or can social research be subjected to the scientific method?

These and allied questions bordering on the scope and limits of application of scientific paradigms in the study of social reality have engaged the minds of philosophers for centuries. Thus, an attempt to problematise and tackle the immanent problems in the social sciences would involve a combination of historical, theoretical and conceptual analysis of the trajectories of the discourse.

The philosophy of the social sciences poses the fundamental question or problem of interrogating the extent to which the themes (subject, ideas), the logic and the methods of the social sciences are distinctive and peculiar as basis of differentiating the social sciences from the human sciences on the one hand, and for associating the social sciences with the natural sciences on the other hand. The challenge placed squarely before the practitioners of the social sciences is to explain to us what is veritably scientific about their vocations. Philosophers of the social sciences intend to establish how well the instruments and values of the natural sciences could conceivably and actually be applied to the social world.

To what extent can we hope to apply in a hard headed manner the stringent and disciplinary matrices of the natural sciences in fulfilling the scientific goals of:
·                     Understanding
·                     Explanation
·                     Prediction and
·                     Control, on human agents whose actions are guided by desires, wills and emotion? How in short, can we explain and predict or even control fluid human behaviour using objective scientific paradigms? The crucial point to be made and restates is that the social sciences insofar as they claim to be scientific must prove two things to us:

1.                  Whether they are scientific in the way the natural sciences are scientific (A methodological question)

2.                  Whether it is really the case that human social experience given its variations and fluidity is truly susceptible to scientific understanding and analysis? (This raises a thematic issue).

F    Philosophers and the Social Sciences

Philosophers of the social sciences have also grappled with another major problem which is a problem that also arises in the philosophy of science. The problem has to do with the reducibility of the social. This problem is not to fare removed from the central problem of the social sciences which is as to whether the social sciences actually are, or should be natural sciences. The problem of reducibility raises the question as to whether the social sciences is indeed reducible to the individual, and if this is so, might not the individual person be reducible in turn to purely physical matters? Might not the social sciences, then, be not only essentially similar to, but ultimately derivable, at least in principle from the physical sciences? The affirmation of both of these theses about the social sciences constitutes what may be called scientism

F    J. S. Mill: A Proponent of the Systematization of Facts.
J.S. Mill was a British utilitarian philosopher and economist. Mill was convinced that it is possible to carry out social investigation through the method of the natural sciences. The social scientists only need to ape the methods and approaches of the natural sciences. Mill’s thesis came in the context of the 19th century surge towards scientism. The attraction to scientism is in turn a by-product of the unprecedented and spectacular successes of the natural sciences since the 1600s. Hence the demand for a sciences of society, and in fact, numerous claims to have established it from such writers and theorists as Auguste Comte, Karl Marx and Herbert Spencer. But by far the clearest, most carful, subtlest and most comprehensive articulator of the scientistic position was that of J. Mill.
According to Mill, nature is defined by uniformity. In other words, for Mill, all the phenomena in the world conform to specific regularities. The most fundamental of these regularities are called Laws of Nature. It then becomes the task of science to discover these uniformities which are of two kinds:
1.                  The uniformities of coexistence and
2.                  The uniformities of successions.
To understand Mill properly, the laws of nature are used in explaining things in reality. These laws of nature are physical laws which have undergone experimental verification and are consequently developed by the natural sciences. These laws are subdivided in the manner stated above. And for Mill, the laws of succession are more important because they are causal laws. A causal law interconnects the antecedent and the consequent. And again, for Mill the natural world is governed by the principles of causality or universal causation.
Mill goes on to identify induction as the basic principle scientists apply in discovering and proving general propositions. Mill defines induction here in terms of what he calls “Method of Difference –that is observation of the difference made by experimentally controlled presence or absence of a given factor in otherwise constant conditions. But as Mill immediately saw, the internal complexity and contradictions of interacting causes often undermines the usefulness of the inductive method. Thus, for Mill, the scientist then introduces the deductive method. The deductive method must then begin from the relevant causal laws, inductively established, to attempt to deduce from these causal laws the effect of their joint action in given combinations.
But as Mill admits, such a calculation is subject to various uncertainties and so its results must be tested by further step, which he calls “verification.” Following verification, (deductively) conclusions must be found by careful comparison to accord with the results of direct observation. Uniformities thus deductively arrived at, which also accord with experiences may be considered as laws.
F    Mill on the Social Sciences: There is a Science of Human Nature.
Mill’s views on the social sciences derive from his general view on nature and the nature of the human mind. According to him, there is, or at least there may be and should be a science of human nature, in the same way we have a science of nature generally. The most fundamental laws to be found in the science of human nature, Mill continues, are inductively certified laws – laws of the Mind, that is, laws stating casual regularities. To be able to arrive at these laws that state and explain causal regularities is important, because for Mill, this would help us to determine states of mind in individuals with accuracy. More than anything else, these laws would form the basis of the science of psychology.
Prominent among these laws are laws governing the association of ideas. To be sure, says Mill, several deductive sciences are derivable from the basic laws of Mind (just as they are, in the case of the physical sciences, from the basic law of Mechanic). One such is Ethology, the science of the formation of individual character, to be obtained by deducing the effects of the laws of Mind in particular circumstances. Another is what Mill calls the ‘social science’ or sociology which is the understanding of the action and feelings of human beings in the social state as entirely governed by psychological and ethnological laws.
As a matter of fact, it would be more accurate to talk about Mill’s social science in plural, because Mill distinguished between two categories of social sciences:
1.                  A general science of society

2.                  A special or separate ‘abstract’ science dealing with particular areas of social life, in which (as is sometimes though not typically the case) human action is mainly governed by one single law of human nature; one single human passion or motive or desire. Thus for example, the science of political economy is a deduction from men’s desire of wealth – and from that desire (almost) alone. Mill was careful to stress both the validity of this social science and its limitations. It is valid because although it is not generally true that social life is ever wholly governed by the desire for wealth, it is sufficiently close to the truth I the area of economic production and distribution.
Its validity, therefore, is limited to this area; and even in this area, its laws are only an approximation to the truth. And there is a further limitation: the laws of political economy are valid, even in the economic sphere only in particular states of society; i.e., particular societies in a particular stage of historical development, states of society where the science’s assumptions both about motivation and about relevant social circumstances hold (at least approximately) true.
Mill was well aware that this is far from being universally the case; thus we cannot arrive by deduction, ‘at any great number of propositions which will be true in all societies without exception’, because of the eminently modified nature of the social phenomena, and the multitude and verity of the circumstances by which they are modified.
In summary, Mill’s scientism consists, above all, in his belief that all nature, including human nature and therefore man’s social life is governed by causal laws discoverable by induction and deduction. But the question that arises for Mill is; ‘are the laws of human nature in turn, ultimately derivable from physical laws? Mill considered this to be extremely probable, but not yet conclusively proved and to this extent, his scientism (unlike that of Comte) is less than total. Laws of Mind, he claims are discoverable in their own right, and are the proper basis of the moral sciences.
It is worth pointing out, in the end, that Mill’s particular brand of sociological scientism is:
1.                  Individualistic: sociological laws are held to be deducible from laws of Mind and of ethology having reference to the motives, actions and characters of individuals;

2.                  Mentalistic: (Clearly so); Mill shows……………………
Status of mental phenomenon as object of scientific study, indeed his fundamental laws of human nature are, precisely, laws of Mind.
F    Japan and the World War II
In February 1933, Japan withdrew from the League of the Nations, at the same time that Western Powers refused to recognize Manchukuo as an Independent State under Japanese Military auspices. These moves were followed by continuous nibbling away at Chinese territory by the Kwantung Army. In April 1933, the Japanese signed the Tanggu (Tangku) truce with the Chinese government which extended Japanese area of occupation to the Great Wall.
F    Pearl Harbor
Knoe Cabinet in 1940, following the fall of France to the Nazi and the weakening of the European Powers, announced its intention to create a “Great East Asian Co-Prosperity Sphere,” a regional block centering on Japan that would include French Indo-China and Dutch East Indies and other European colonial territories as well as Manchukuo and China. This followed an overwhelming vote to strengthen ties with the Axis Powers – Germany and Italy. In September 1941, the …. Government signed the Axis Pact, a tripartite mutual agreement treaty with Germany and Italy as deterrence to the US not to intervene in the European War or the Sino-Japanese Conflict. Roosevelt administration disapproved of Japanese aggression in China and kicked against an epidemic of World Lawlessness and Japan spoke of Liberating Asia from Western Imperialism.
F    Economy
By the mid 1930s, the US supplied nearly one-third of all Japanese import including goods critical to Military mobilization. Japan was consequently vulnerable to American economic pressure. In the summer of 1938, Washington placed a voluntary “Moral embargo” on shipments of aircrafts, arms, and other War materials to Japan in July 1939, it abrogated its commercial treaty with Japan in anticipation of expanded economic warfare, and in 1940, the President restricted the export of aviation Moto fuel, scrap iron, and steel to Japan.
Japan simply could not fathom American’s idealism – their support of China with whom they had little economic interests. Through Nomura Kichisaburo, Japan sought to end the Chinese aggression under certain conditions:
1.                  A negotiated withdrawal of Japanese troops from China; Chinese recognition of Manchukuo’s independence; a merger between the Chiang government and the puppet region at Nanjing under Wang Jingwei; and a Joint Sino-Japanese anti Soviet Pact. America rejected all of these, insisting on a return to the 1931 Statues.
Japan then tried to mend fence with the Soviets following the routing of the Kwantung Army near the Manchukuo border in 1931. But in august 1931, Stalin signed a Non-aggression Pact with Hitler, making the Japanese fear less o the Soviet. The Japanese then began to mount major offensive in Southern Indo-China in preparation for attacks on the Dutch East Indies.
As a result, the Roosevelt administration froze Japanese assets in the US and imposed an embargo on oil exports to Japan. Great Britain, the Commonwealth nations, and the government of Dutch East Indies followed suit, cutting 90% of Japan’s petroleum imports. The Japanese war effort would have to be contained somehow. The government of Knoe desired all of these as A B C D (American – British –Chinese – Dutch) encirclement of Japan. Seizing the oil wells in the Dutch Indies became the only Japanese opportunity but doing this would lead to an inevitable war with the US. But Japan was not ready to play second field with White Imperialist Powers, so in September 1941, decided to go to war with the US by late October. As a last desperate effort to stop the war, Knoe proposes a direct conference with Roosevelt, who declined, following which Knoe resigned and Tojd Hideki, an outspoken military war monger since 1930s took over as Prime Minister.
Again the Tojo government proposed to withdraw from Indo-China if US agrees to end the oil embargo, help Japan get oil from supplies from the Indies and assist Japan in achieving diplomatic end to hostilities in China.   But in November 1941, the Roosevelt administration once again restated its earlier commitment to respect for international law and sovereignty: it would accept nothing less than a return to the Pre 1931 status quo, the withdrawal of Japanese troops from China, Manchukuo and Indo-China, and Japanese recognition of the Chiang Kai-shek government. The irresistible force had met an unmovable object.
On Sunday, December 7, while secretaries in the Japanese embassy at Washington rushed to finish typing a translation of the final note breaking off relations with US, carrier-based Japanese planes swept out of the sky in a surprise attack on the naval base at Pearl Harbor, inflicting heavy damages on the American Pacific Fleet. The “Wanted, Unwanted War” had begun.

v    18/4/2011

Logical positivism signifies a philosophical movement developed in the 1920s by some analytic-minded scholars who developed a criterion of significance – the verifiability principle – as a means of ridding philosophy of what they regarded as its metaphysical, non-scientific, impurities. This school recognized two categories of significant statements namely (1) statements which are empirically variable (directly or indirectly) (2) analytic statements which are true in virtue of the meaning of their terms. The quest for what justifies scientific belief over metaphysical and religious beliefs was therefore the moving spirit of the logical positivists. The logical positivists were concerned with setting out the necessary and sufficient conditions under which a statement could be said to be genuinely meaningful, and hence to be either true or false. More specifically, the main objective of the logical positivists can be outlined as follows:

1.                  To identify the difference between the formal and empirical sciences, and to note the character of the “formal truths” which derives from former sort of sciences as against the “factual truths” of the empirical sciences.

2.                  To formulate the principle of verification, or the verification criterion of meaning which would serve as a means of distinguishing between genuine and pseudo statements or sciences, etc.

F    Kun: Critical Advocate of Changing Paradigms.
Despite the high esteem in which they held science the positivists paid little attention to the history of science. Indeed, they believed that philosophers had little to learn from studying history of science. This was primarily because they draw a sharp distinction between what they called the ‘context of discovery’ and the ‘context of justification’. The context of discovery refers to the actual historical process by which a scientist arrives at a given theory. The context of justification refers to the means by which the scientist tries to justify his theory once it is already there – which includes testing the theory, searching for relevant evidence, and so on.

 The positivists believed that the former was a subjective, psychological process that wasn’t governed by precise rules, while the latter was an objective matter of logic. Philosophers of science should confine themselves to studying the latter, they argued. This sharp distinction between discovery and justification, and the belief that the former is ‘subjective’ and ‘psychological’ while the latter is not, explains why the positivists’ approach to philosophy of science was so ahistorical. For the actual historical process by which scientific ideas change and develop lies squarely in the context of discovery, not the context of justification. That process might be of interest to historians or psychologists, but had nothing to teach philosophers of science, according to the positivists.

·                     The acceptance of positivists’ position would imply that the scientific enterprise is a value-neutral inquiry – meaning that theory choice is an objective thing. Value-neutral means that biases, personal opinions and sentiments do not count. Consequently, if two or more theories conflicts, it is possible to choose which one is better because there is such a thing as value-neutral-data, meaning raw data that rival scientific groups could analyze to arrive at objective conclusion.
This means that science is an objective activity. It could also mean that science is a universal activity; thereby making science a rational inquiry. Science becomes therefore the authentic means of acquiring the truth out there in the world.

F    Kun: Post Positivists’ Philosophy of Science.

Kun was a historian of science by training, and firmly believed that philosophers had much to learn from studying the history of science. Insufficient attention to the history of science had led the positivists to form an inaccurate and naïve picture of the scientific enterprise, he maintained.
According to Kun, there is nothing like value-neutral-data, instead there is a value-ladenness of data. Again, according to him, it is not possible to compare two rival theories. According to Kun, when an existing paradigm is replaced by a new one in a scientific revolution, scientists have to abandon the whole conceptual framework which they use to make sense of the world. Indeed, Kun even claims that before and after a paradigm shift, scientists ‘live in different worlds’.
Incommensurability is the idea that two paradigms may be so different as to render impossible any straightforward comparison of them with each other – there is no common ground into which both can be translated. As a result, the proponents of different paradigms ‘fail to make common place contact with each other’s viewpoint’, Kun claimed.

The doctrine of incommensurability stems from Kun’s belief that scientific concepts derive their meaning from the theory in which they play a role. To understand Newton’s concept of mass, for example, we need to understand the whole of Newtonian theory – concepts cannot be explained independently of the theories in which they are embedded. This idea, which is sometimes called ‘holism’, was taken seriously by Kun. He argued that the term ‘mass’ actually meant something different for Newton and Einstein, since the theories in which each embedded the term we so different. This implies that Newton and Einstein were in effect speaking different languages, which obviously complicates the attempt to choose between their theories. If a Newtonian and an Einsteinian physicist tried to have a rational discussion, they would end up taking past each other.

Kun used the incommensurability thesis both too rebut the view that paradigm shifts are fully ‘objective’, and to bolster his non-cumulative picture of the history of science. Traditional philosophy of science saw no huge difficulty in choosing between competing theories – you simply make an objective comparison of them, in the light of the available evidence, and decide which is better. But this clearly presumes that there is a common language in which both theories can be expressed. If Kun is right that proponents of old and new paradigms are quite literally talking past each other, no such simplistic account of paradigm choice can be correct.

If old and new paradigms are incommensurable, then, it cannot be correct to think of scientific revolutions as the replacement of ‘wrong’ ideas by ‘right’ ones. For to call an idea right and another wrong implies the existence of a common framework for evaluating them, which is precisely what Kun denies. Incommensurability implies that scientific change, far from being a straightforward progress towards the truth, is in a sense directionless: later paradigms are not better than earlier ones, just different.

Not many philosophers were convinced by Kun’s incommensurability thesis. Part of it was that Kun also claimed old and new paradigms to be incompatible. If old and new paradigms were not compatible there would be no need to choose between them. If the doctrine of incommensurability is right, then, there is no actual disagreement between Newton and Einstein, for the proposition means something different for each. Only if the proposition has the same meaning in both theories, i.e., only if there is no incommensurability, is there a genuine conflict between the two.

F    Theory Ladenness

Suppose you are a scientist trying to choose between two conflicting theories. The obvious thing to do is to look for a piece of data that will decide between the two – which is just what traditional philosophy of science recommended. But this will only be possible if there exists data that are independent of the theories, in the sense that a scientist would accept the data whichever of the two theories he believes. The logical positivists believed in the existence of such theory-neutral data, which could provide an objective court of appeal between competing theories.  But Kun argued that the ideal of theory –neutrality is an illusion – data are invariably contaminated by theoretical assumption. It is impossible to isolate a set of ‘pure’ data which all scientists would accept irrespective of their theoretical persuasion.

The theory-ladenness of data had two consequences for Kun. Firstly, it means that the issue of between competing paradigms could not be resolved by simply appealing to ‘the data’ or ‘the facts’, for what a scientist counts as data, or fact, will depend on which paradigm she accepts. Perfectly objective choices between two paradigms are therefore impossible: there is no neutral vantage-point from which to assess the claims of each. Secondly, the very idea of objective truth is called into question; for to be objectively true, our theories or beliefs must correspond to the facts, but the idea of such a correspondence makes little sense if the facts themselves are inferred by our theories. This is why Kun was led to radical view that truth itself is relative to a paradigm.

Why did Kun think that all data are theory-laden? The first is the idea that perception is heavily conditioned by background beliefs – what we see depends in part on what we believe. A trained scientist for example, looking at a sophisticated piece apparatus in a laboratory will see something different from what a layman sees, for the scientist obviously has many beliefs about the apparatus that the layman lacks. Secondly, scientists’ experimental and observational reports are often couched n highly theoretical language. For example, a scientist might report the outcome of an experiment by saying “an electric current is flowing through the copper rod’. But this data report is obviously laden with a large amount of theory. It would not be accepted by a scientist who did not hold standard beliefs about electric currents, so it is clearly not theory-neutral.

F    Kun’s Scientific Revolution

Kun was especially interested in scientific revolution – periods of great upheaval when existing scientific ideas are replaced with radically new ones. Examples of scientific revolutions are the Copernican revolution in astronomy, the Eisteninan revolution in physics, and the Darwinian revolution in biology. Each of these revolutions led to a fundamental change in the scientific world-view – the overthrow of an existing set of ideas by a completely different set.

Scientific revolutions happen relatively infrequently – most of the time any given science is not in a state of revolution. Kun therefore coined the term ‘normal science’ to describe the ordinary day-to-day activities that scientists engage in when their discipline is not undergoing revolutionary change. Central to Kun’s account of normal science is the concept of paradigm. A paradigm consists of two main components:

1.                    Firstly, a set of fundamental theoretical assumptions that all members of a scientific community accepts at a given time;

2.                  Secondary, a set of ‘exemplars’ or ‘particular scientific problems that have been solved by means of those theoretical assumptions, and that appears in the textbooks if the discipline in question.

But a paradigm is more than just a theory. When scientists share a paradigm, they do not just agree on certain scientific propositions. They also agree on how future scientific research in their filed should proceed, on which problem are the pertinent ones to tackle, on what the appropriate method for solving those problems are, on what an acceptable solution of the problems would look like, and so on. In short, a paradigm is an entire outlook – a constellation of shared assumptions, beliefs, and values that unite a scientific community and allow normal science to take place. According to Kun, normal science is primarily a matter of puzzle-solving.

However successful a paradigm is, it will always encounter certain problems – phenomena that it cannot easily accommodate, mismatches between the theory’s predictions and the experimental facts, and so on. The job of the normal scientist is to try to eliminate these minor puzzles while making as few changes as possible to the paradigm. So normal science is highly conservative activity – its practitioners are not trying to make any earth-shattering discoveries, but rather just to develop and extend the existing paradigm. In Kun’s words, ‘normal science does not aim at novelties of fact or theory, and when successful finds none’.

Above all, Kun stressed that normal scientists are not trying to test the paradigm. On the contrary, they accept the paradigm unquestioningly, and conduct their research within the limits it sets. If a normal scientist gets an experimental result that conflict with the paradigm, she will usually assume that her experimental techniques are faulty, not that the paradigm is wrong. The paradigm itself is not negotiable.

Typically, a period of normal science lasts many decades, sometimes even centuries. During this time scientists gradually articulate that paradigm – fine-tuning it, filling in details, solving more and more puzzles, extending its range of application, and so on. But over time anomalies are discovered – phenomena that simply cannot be reconciled with the theoretical assumptions of the paradigm, however hard normal scientists try. When anomalies are few in number they tend to just get ignored. But as more and more anomalies accumulate, a burgeoning sense of crisis envelops the scientific community. Confidence in the existing paradigm breaks down, and the process of normal science temporarily grand to a halt. This marks the beginning of a period of ‘revolutionary science’.

During such periods, fundamental scientific ideas are up for grab. A variety of alternatives to the old paradigm are proposed, and eventually a new paradigm becomes established. A generation or so is usually required before members of the scientific community are won over to the new paradigm – an event that marks the completion of a scientific revolution. The essence of a scientific revolution is the shift from an old paradigm to a new one.

Ordinarily we assume that when scientists trade their existing theory for new one, they do so on the basis of objective evidence. Kun however argues that adopting a new paradigm involves a certain act of faith on the part of the scientists. He allowed that a scientist could have good reasons for abandoning an old paradigm for a new one, but he insisted that reason alone could never rationally compel a paradigm shift. The transfer of allegiance from paradigm to paradigm, Kun maintained, ‘is a conversion experience which cannot be forced’.  A new paradigm indeed gains acceptance in the scientific community through peer pressure of scientists on one another, forceful advocates and the right political will.

F    Critique

If paradigm shift works the way Kun says, it is hard to see how science can be regarded as a rational activity at all. Surely scientists are meant to base their beliefs on evidence and reason, not on faith and peer pressure. Faced with two competing paradigms, surely the scientists should make an objective comparison of them to determine which has more evidence on its favour. Undergoing a ‘conversion experience’, or allowing oneself to be persuaded by the more forceful one’s fellow scientists, hardly seems like a rational way to behave. Kun’s account of paradigm shifs seems hard to reconcile with the familiar positivist image of science as an objective, rational activity. One critic wrote that on Kun’s account, theory choice in science was ‘a matter of mob psychology’.

v    9/5/2011

F    The Kantian Defence of Induction

Kant (1724 – 1804)

Kant is regarded as the greatest philosopher in modern times and in fact can be pared in the rank of Plato and Aristotle. It was Kant that situated Epistemology at the center of philosophy in the modern era. Kant was also a quintessential philosopher of science and he majored in Newtonian physics.

Going back to what Kant said that it was Hume who woke him from his dogmatic slumber, as such this gave rise to Kant’s effort in distinguishing and mediating between analytic – synthetic dichotomy. This dichotomy was brought about by Leibniz and then Hume before Kant. This is what Hume calls exhaustive dichotomy between meaningful propositions.

For Hume therefore, analytic propositions are a priori, relations of ideas, they are tautologous and do not give us new knowledge. Whereas synthetic proposition are empirical or matters of facts and the object is not implicit in the subject. That is, they give us new knowledge.

Kant saw the problem in Hume’s philosophy that he had actually destroyed/dismantled philosophy. He wondered therefore on how best to salvage science and of course Newtonian physics. He went further to establish that metaphysical phenomena and the sciences, human free-will can be proven. For instance, metaphysical phenomena like God, spirits, human free-will, and sciences can be proven.

Induction at the end of the day cannot give us conclusive evidence, says Hume and that is the major problem of Hume. For him therefore, induction can only be probable. In the light of the above, Kant proffered another edifice to lay a strong foundation for philosophy.

·                     Like Berkeley and Leibniz, before him, Kant was concerned with how a world governed by deterministic causal laws could in turn accommodate human free-will and God’s existence, and intervention. Whereas Berkeley and Leibniz sought to resolve this conflict by down-grading the ‘pretentions’ of the physical sciences, denying their basic tenets, equal status with metaphysical doctrines; on the other hand, Kant thought the physical sciences has made greater and consistent progress, where philosophy had floundered in chaos. Philosophers routinely disagree with one another, and generally ended up refuting every other theory.

Kant also tackled Hume’s challenge to philosophy. If Leibniz/Hume’s distinction was right, then, for Kant, philosophy itself was in a serious predicament. This is so because on the one hand, philosophy does not put itself across as an empirical science based on observation and experiment, neither would it wish to concede that all it was doing was elaborating a set of tautologies, analyzing the terms in which we speak and think. Hume’s question was: “What else could a philosopher possibly be doing, if he is not doing neither of the two?

The greater problem as Kant identified was that dividing propositions exhaustively into those two classes (synthetic or analytic) meant that every general scientific laws fall outside the gamut of meaningful propositions; since they are neither analytic nor straight-forwardly factual – they can’t be deductively arrived at by logic nor can they be proved from experience. this of course led to Hume’s problem of induction since for Hume inductive statements or propositions are neither analytic nor factual (i.e., they do not belong to relation of ideas or to matters of fact). Inductive statements or causal laws are not tautologies; neither could they be proven from experience. In the end, however, Hume thought that the thought that the sciences could carry on well simply as a body of empirical hypothesis without any claim of constituting a sustainable body of knowledge.

Kant thought that Hume’s traditional philosophy was mistaken. To demonstrate this, Kant introduced the notion of synthetic a priori proposition. According to Kant, the synthetic – a priori propositions are not merely analytic but at the same time not contingent either. In other words, for Kant, synthetic a priori propositions are both synthetic and necessary as well. Kant felt sure that he could point to propositions both in the natural sciences and mathematics which are not analytic, but were not empirical and contingent either. These are statements which apply to the world but could not be derived from experience/observation of the world. But the question is this: “How do we arrive at synthetic a priori proposition given their very nature?”

From here it became very important for Kant to make important distinction. Kant makes a distinction between ‘things –in – themselves’ or the ‘world – in – itself’ and ‘things – as – they appear to us’ (appearances). To be sure, we cannot unravel the noumenal[1] world (things – in – themselves) but as for the phenomenal[2] world (the world as it appears to us), there are conditions every knowable world must conform to in order to be intelligible to anybody or us. For Kant, finally, perceiving subject can only know those things which their a priori concepts or predispositions can accommodate or experience given the fact that our knowable world possesses those internal matrices that renders it intelligible to our sensory, intellectual and conceptual capabilities. What Kant achieved here as novel was setting down the necessary condition of the very possibility of experience.

Leibniz and Hume, according to Kant had been wrong in insisting that all meaningful propositions must on the one hand be either analytic and a priori (i.e. true or false by the nature of the terms used and the rules governing their use and thus knowable in advance of their external application); or on the other hand synthetic and a posteriori (i.e., true or false according to how things are observed to be in the empirical external world and therefore knowable only after the event because such knowledge depends on experience).

For Kant, we have propositions of a 3rd kind, synthetic, yet a priori, which are about the world yet are not validated by experience: true or false about the world yet knowable in advance. For example, Space and Time do not characterize things as they are in themselves but are inescapable modes of experience for us. They are not independently existent, but are the only dimensions through which we can experience the world. They are bodies of knowledge, the knowledge they give us is given to us in advance of any possible application in experience, they are synthetic a priori.

v    Space

Space dictate form is provided by geometry and time by arithmetic. Space and time spell out forms of sensibility. But Kant thought of what he called forms of the understanding, or forms of thoughts. The fundamental assumption here is that any possible world of experience, and any world about which objective statement can be made are sometimes known to true and must necessarily in certain respects be orderly and predictable. From here, Kant tried to show that if his claims above are right, then Newtonian principle of universal causal determinism or quite simply induction was true.

In summation, Kant’s philosophy is that since our perceptions and experiences came to us through our sensory and mental apparatus, they all come to us in forms which are sense-dependent and mind-dependent. We really never can know things-in-themselves; our knowledge of things are constantly mediated by the Forms of sensibility and the Forms of Understanding, knowledge for Kant is therefore restricted by ‘possible experience.’ From here Kant believed that his critical mediation between Rationalism and Empiricism was complete.





v    16/5/2011

F    John Stuart Mill’s System of Logic – “Proving the Science of Human Nature”

The view that the sciences offer authentic knowledge and therefore that the method of science is the best means of acquiring or providing reliable knowledge, not just in the sciences but in every other field of learning, including for example the social sciences is called “Scientism”. This view says that the method of science could be and should be aped by other fields of learning in other to make the kind of progress we see in science. Put differently, scientism is the view that science provides reliable knowledge. The philosophy of the social sciences is precisely an attempt to raise questions about the scientist’s view, i.e., critical methodological, theoretical questions about the scienticist’s position.

Philosophy of the social sciences is an attempt to interrogate, subject the assumptions behind scientism to critical scrutiny. Put simply, philosophy of the social sciences asks the question: “Is scientism true?” One major proponent of scientism, a British Utilitarian philosopher and economist is John Stuart Mill. He assumed that for us to accept the view that scientism or scientific endeavour is true, is if the claim of induction is true, or if it is impossible that induction is true, those could be a reinforcement if induction which  is the systematic theory of Logic, i.e. proving the science of the human mind. If we develop the science of the human mind, we could predict the future. For Mill, this is to provide metaphysical foundation for studying human nature that could bring about the contingencies of history in every epoch.


[1] Independent object in Kantian Philosophy. In Kantian philosophy, something that exists independently of intellectual or sensory perception of it, e.g. the soul in some beliefs.


[2]  Philosophy – perceived by the senses: perceived by the senses, rather than the mind, and thus having at least an apparent external existence.


Comments

Popular posts from this blog

SUMMARY OF PROVIDENTISSIMUS DEUS, ENCYCLICAL LETTER OF POPE LEO XIII ON THE STUDY OF THE HOLY SCRIPTURE.

summary and appraisal of chapters one, two and three of the book The African Origin of Greek Philosophy: An Exercise in Afrocentrism, by Innocent C. Onyewuenyi.

THE LAST THREE WAYS TO PROVES GOD'S EXISTENCE BY THOMAS AQUINAS