PROGRESS IN SCIENCE, REVOLUTION AND RATIONALITY.


1.0       Introduction
The progressive nature of science is one attribute that is often used to distinguish it from other domains of human culture like philosophy, religion, art and politics. Improvements and advances in science are identifiable because of the presence of clear standards or normative criteria for identifying such progress. Most historians of science hold the view that progress has no universally recognized and definite meaning in other fields than in the field of science. But debates on the normative concept of scientific progress have often led to the following questions: What is meant by progress in science? How can we recognize this progress? To what extent, and in which respects, is science progressive? While traditional philosophers of science like Popper saw “development-by-accumulation” of accepted facts and theories as the yardstick for progress in science, Thomas Khun, on the other hand came to realize that traditional accounts, do not bear comparison with historical evidence.[1] In his book The Structure of Scientific Progress, Kuhn rejected the notion that scientific progress is cumulative and argued that there are periods in which such conceptual continuity in normal science were interrupted by periods of revolutionary science.
            In this paper, we shall first discuss the various approaches taken by different philosophers of science to define the nature of scientific progress or what makes science progressive. After which we shall take a closer look at Kuhn’s approach to scientific progress which lays more emphasis on the revolutionary nature of science. We shall also explicate terms like paradigm, normal science and incommensurability which have been popularized by Kuhn’s work.
2.0       Basic Approaches Used in Characterizing Scientific Progress
            There are three general approaches that have been used by philosophers of science to define scientific progress: 1) the epistemic approach; 2) the semantic approach; 3) the functional-internalist approach.[2] According to the epistemic approach, science makes progress precisely when it shows the accumulation of scientific knowledge. That is, an episode in science is progressive when at the end of the episode, there is more knowledge than at the beginning. This view was held by logical empiricists like Rudolf Carnap who sees scientific advancement as the discovery of higher-level laws or theories which deductively entail lower-level ones.[3] The semantic approach on the other hand defines scientific progress in terms of accumulation of true scientific belief (truth-likeness or verisimilitude) instead of increasing knowledge. According to Karl Popper, verisimilitude represents the idea of approaching comprehensive truth. He opines that even when theories are false, they can be cognitively valuable if they are closer to the truth than their rivals.[4] The third approach, which is the functional-internalist approach, was a sharp deviation from the other two approaches. Thomas Kuhn was one of the major philosophers of science who propagated this approach. He opines that progress is made when a scientific development succeeds in fulfilling a certain function (such as solving a scientific problem), where that function is understood in such a way that the scientific practitioners are themselves in a position to judge whether the function has been fulfilled.[5] Kuhn rejects the cumulative notion of progressive science held by both the epistemic and semantic approach.
3.0       Traditional View of Scientific Progress
Despite the disagreements between Karl Popper and the logical positivists, they all shared the following similar views about the nature of science[6]: 1) Science is cumulative. That is, scientists build on the achievements of their predecessor (growth in knowledge or truth); 2) Science is unified in the sense that there exist only one set of fundamental methods for all the sciences and that all natural sciences are reducible to physics (reductionism) since everything in the world is made up of the same basic stuff in their complex combination; 3) There is a distinction between context of discovery and context of justification. This means that the evidence for scientific knowledge ought to be evaluated without reference to the causal origins of the theories or observations; 4) There is an underlying logic of confirmation or falsification implicit in all scientific evaluations of the evidence for some hypothesis and such evaluations are value-free, that is independent of the personal non-scientific view of the scientists; 5) There is a sharp distinction (demarcation) between scientific theories and other types belief system; 6) There is a sharp distinction between observation terms and theoretical terms, and also between theoretical terms and those that describe the result of experiment; 7) Scientific terms have fixed and precise meaning.
In his book, The Structure of Scientific Revolution, Kuhn challenged these prevailing views and rejected them. But before we look at how he refutes these views, we shall first discuss some central ideas he used in the explication of his idea of scientific progress or scientific revolution.
4.0       Paradigm and Normal Science
The most fundamental concept in Kuhn’s philosophy is that of the scientific paradigm. According to Kuhn, a paradigm is that which co-ordinates and directs the puzzle-solving activities of the groups of normal scientists that work within it by setting the standards for legitimate work within the science it governs.[7] Kuhn explained what a paradigm meant using two senses: those of paradigm as disciplinary matrix and paradigm as exemplar. He argues that before a scientific inquiry can even begin in some domain, the scientific community involved has to agree upon answers to fundamental questions like what kind of things exist in the universe and how they interact with each other and our senses.[8]
A disciplinary matrix is a set of answers to such questions that are learned by scientists in the course of research, and that provide the framework within which the science operates. It is also referred to as a set of commitments shared by practitioners of a particular scientific field, including a special vocabulary and established experimental techniques, as well as accepted theoretical claims.[9] It is also important that some aspects of this matrix will consist of practical skills and methods that are not necessarily expressible in words. Exemplars, on the other hand, involve those successful parts of science that all beginning scientists learn, and which provide them with a model for the future development of their subject. There is no doubt that teaching by example plays a vital role in the training of scientists, and it is through this means that scientists effectively acquire and apply new techniques to solve new kinds of problem.[10] According to Kuhn, it is the existence of a paradigm capable of supporting a normal science tradition that distinguishes science from non-science. Newtonian mechanics and wave optics constitute paradigms and qualify as science. Much of modern sociology lacks a paradigm and consequently fails to qualify as science.[11]
Most science is what Kuhn calls “normal science”, because it is conducted within an established paradigm. He portrays normal science as a puzzle-solving activity governed by the rules of a paradigm.[12] It involves detailed attempts to articulate a paradigm with the aim of improving the match between it and nature. A mature science is governed by a single paradigm which co-ordinates and directs the puzzle-solving activity of normal scientists that work within it. Prior to normal science is what Kuhn calls “pre-science” in which there is no consensus on any particular theory, though the research carried out can be considered scientific in nature. They are the disorganized and diverse activity that precedes the formation of a normal science.[13] An example of a normal science is the coming up with more detailed predictions and experimental determinations of the paths of planet and other heavenly bodies.[14] Periods of normal science provide the opportunity for scientists to solve the difficult details of a theory.
4.1       Crisis and Revolution
            Kuhn is very critical of Popper’s falsification, according to which scientists do and should abandon any refuted theory. For Kuhn, the knowledge of falsifying instances is not enough to make scientists abandon their theories.[15] He recognizes that paradigms will always encounter some difficulties or anomalies. But the mere existence of anomalies (unsolved puzzles) within a paradigm does not constitute a crisis.[16] Some anomalies may be dismissed as errors in observation, others as merely requiring small adjustments to the current paradigm that will be clarified in due course. Some anomalies resolve themselves spontaneously, having increased the available depth of insight along the way. But no matter how numerous the anomalies that persist, Kuhn observes that the practicing scientists will not lose faith in the established paradigm for as long as no credible alternative is available. It is only under special sets of conditions that the anomalies can develop in such a way as to undermine confidence in the paradigm. An anomaly will be regarded as particularly serious if it is seen as striking at the very fundamentals of a paradigm and yet persistently resists attempts by the members of the normal scientific community to remove it.[17] The length of time that an anomaly resists attempts to remove it will also bear on its seriousness.
            When anomalies come to be seen as posing serious problems for a paradigm, a period of crisis sets in. Once a paradigm has been weakened to such an extent that its proponents lose their confidence in it, the time is ripe for revolution. The seriousness of a crisis deepens when a rival paradigm makes its appearance. The new paradigm will be very different and incompatible with the old one. Kuhn argues that there is always a radical difference between the new and the old paradigm. Each paradigm will regard the world as being made up of different kinds of things. This is because the way scientists view a particular aspect of the world will be guided by a paradigm in which they are working. Rival paradigms pose different kinds of question and involve different and incompatible standards. Kuhn likened the change of allegiance on the part of individual scientists from one paradigm to an incompatible alternative to a “gestalt switch” or a “religious conversion” of which none can claim superiority over the other.[18]
            According to Kuhn, a scientific revolution corresponds to the abandonment of one paradigm and the adoption of a new one, not by an individual scientist only but by the relevant scientific community as a whole.[19] When this occurs, a “paradigm shift” is said to take place. In Kuhn’s view, when a revolution occurs the old paradigm is replaced wholesale.[20] The new paradigm gradually succeeds in attracting a group of followers who amplify the early successes in the new paradigm that competes for allegiance with the old one. Paradigm change is noncumulative because it involves change in scientific theories that is not piecemeal but holistic.
5.0       The Copernican Revolution
            What is arguably the most famous example of a revolution in scientific thought is the “Copernican revolution”. The Copernican Revolution was the paradigm shift from the geocentric Ptolemaic model of the heavens, which postulated the Earth at the centre of the galaxy, to the heliocentric model with the Sun at the centre of the Solar System and the Earth revolving round it with other planets.[21] Even though, Copernicus initiated the revolution, he certainly did not complete it. Individuals like Kepler, Galileo, Descartes and others were motivated to adopt and work on the new paradigm by quite different reasons, even when the Copernican paradigm was not yet fully developed, and when it faced many unsolved problem. It was Isaac Newton who arguably finished the Copernican revolution by providing a consistent physical explanation which showed that the planets are kept in their orbits by the familiar force of gravity.
            Kuhn’s analysis of the Copernican revolution emphasized that, in its beginning, it did not offer more accurate predictions of celestial events, such as planetary positions, than the Ptolemaic system, but instead, appealed to some practitioners based on a promise of better, simpler, solutions that might be developed at some point in the future.
            6.0       Incommensurability
Incommensurability is a term from mathematics which means ‘lack of common measure’.[22] It was adopted by Kuhn and Paul Feyrabend, both of whom argued that successive scientific theories are often incommensurable with each other in the sense that there is no neutral way of comparing their merits. The new paradigm cannot be proven or disproven by the rules of the old paradigm and vice versa.[23] The paradigm shift does not merely involve the revision of an individual theory, it changes the way terminology is defined, how the scientists in that field view their subject, and, perhaps most significantly, what questions are regarded as valid, and what rules are used to determine the truth of a particular theory. The new theories were not, as the scientists had previously thought, just extensions of old theories, but were instead completely new world views.
Kuhn argues that there is no higher standard for comparing theories than the assent of the relevant community, and that the choice between competing paradigms proves to be a choice between incompatible modes of community life.[24] He compares scientific revolution to political revolution because just as there is no legal way to establish which of the two competing factions in a political revolution should be ruler, there is no rational way to settle which of the two competing paradigms in a scientific revolution should be accepted. Hence, any tool to be used by verificationists will be inadequate for the task of deciding between conflicting theories, since it will belong to the very paradigms they seek to compare.[25] Similarly, observations that are intended to falsify a statement will fall under one of the paradigms they are supposed to help compare, and will therefore also be inadequate for the task. Many people have used Kuhn’s arguments to support what philosophers call relativism about scientific knowledge, which is the view that the ‘truths’ of scientific theories are determined in whole or part by social forces.[26]
7.0       How Kuhn’s View of Scientific Progress Differs from Traditional View
            As mentioned above, Kuhn challenged and rejected the seven views held by traditional philosophers of science on the progressive nature of science. On the first view, he argued that the history of science does not consist in the steady accumulation of knowledge, but often involves the wholesale abandonment of past theories. This is because a revolution scientist has a new way of looking at things and solving problems. [27] Kuhn rejects the second view by arguing that theory-testing is not as straightforward as implied because, when experiment conflicts with scientific theory, logic alone does not tell us which of the components of the theoretical system is at fault. Although observation and experience constrain scientific beliefs, they do not singly determine them. Kuhn refutes the third, fourth and sixth views by arguing that the evaluation of theories depends on local historical circumstances, and his analysis of the relationship between theory and observation suggests that theories infect data to such an extent that no way of gathering of observations can ever be theory neutral and objective. Hence, the degree of confirmation an experiment gives to a hypothesis is not objective, and there is no single logic of theory testing that can be used to determine which theory is most justified by the evidence. He thinks, instead, that the value of scientist help determine, not just how individual scientists develop new theories, but also which theories the scientific community as a whole regards as justified. For instance, Einstein (a realist) never accepted quantum mechanics (product of instrumentalism), while many other scientists did, and the dispute between them is not about the empirical evidence in support of the theory, but about what is to be valued in scientific theories. Kuhn points out that psychological and sociological factors play a vital role in determining which paradigm a scientist adopts or rejects.[28]
            Kuhn’s argument against the fifth view is that the same sorts of methods and reasons that lead to scientific knowledge can also be used to produce other belief systems. His argument against the seventh view which says that scientific term have fixed meaning is that theories within different paradigms are incommensurable, in the sense that the terms and concepts of scientific theories in different paradigms are not mutually intertranslatable; this is called meaning incommensurability. Kuhn assumes that scientific terms get their meaning from their position in the structure of a whole theory. For example, ‘mass’ in Newtonian theory means something different from ‘mass’ in Einstein’s relativity theory.[29]
8.0       Progress Through Revolution
            According to Kuhn, there is progress in science when there are revolutions rather than the cumulative progress characteristic of inductivist accounts of science.[30] Since he considered problem solving to be a central element of science, Kuhn saw that for a new candidate for paradigm to be accepted by a scientific community, “First, the new candidate must seem to resolve some outstanding and generally recognized problem that can be met in no other way. Second, the new paradigm must promise to preserve a relatively large part of the concrete problem solving activity that has accrued to science through its predecessors”.[31] And Kuhn maintained that the new paradigm must also solve more problems than its predecessor, which therefore entailed that the number of newly solved problems must be greater than those solved in the old paradigm.
9.0       Rationality, Relativism and Realism
While the rationalist asserts that there is a single, timeless, universal criterion with reference to which the relative merits of rival theories are to be assessed, the relativist on the other hand denies that there is a universal standard of rationality with respect to which one theory can be judged better than another. What counts as better or worse with respect to scientific theories will vary from individual to individual or from community to community.[32] It is important to note that one of the commonest charges directed against Kuhn is that he is a relativist. In this way, Kuhn has been perceived as undermining the notion of scientific truth and even of an objective reality. Hence, there are some people who argue not that scientific knowledge is relative, bur that reality itself is socially constructed[33]. This kind of relativism is believed to be a kind of threat to realism and rationality. Before Kuhn’s work it was common for philosophers to believe that what a particular scientific term, say ‘atom’, refers to is determined by what the theory says about atoms. If this is right, then different theories about ‘atoms’, which say different things about them, will actually refer to different things. This is called reference incommensurability, and it is bad news for realism, for it suggests that different theories about ‘electrons’ are actually all about different things, and hence there is no reason to believe that science has made progress in understanding the underlying nature of things.[34] This seems to imply that there is no one way the world is, but that rather the world we live in is an artefact of our theories about it. Indeed, Kuhn says that ‘when paradigms change the world changes with them and the different languages of different theories correspond to the different worlds. Consequently, we cannot say that Copernicus discovered that Ptolemy and earlier philosophers were wrong to think that the Earth revolves around the Sun, because Copernicus’ Earth is literally a different object from Ptolemy’s.[35]
Kuhn’s work has been viewed by postmodern  thinkers as demonstrating that scientific knowledge is dependent on the culture and historical circumstances of groups of scientists rather than on their adherence to a specific, definable method. His work has also been regarded as blurring the demarcation between scientific and non-scientific enterprises, because it describes the mechanism of scientific progress without invoking any idealized scientific method that is capable of distinguishing science from non-science.
Imre Lakatos criticized Kuhn for treating revolutionary episodes as instances of “mystical conversion”. According to him, Kuhn has portrayed the history of science as an irrational succession of periods of rationality. Lakatos maintained that unless a rational reconstruction of theory replacement can be given, the interpretation of scientific change must be left to historians and psychologists.[36] Popper had produced a rational reconstruction, according to which scientific progress is a sequence of conjectures and attempted refutations. Lakatos sought to improve upon this reconstruction. In particular, he urged that the basic unit for appraisal should be “research programmes” rather than individual theories. According to Lakatos, a research programme consists of methodological rules: some tell us what paths of research to avoid (negative heuristic) and others what paths to pursue (positive heuristic). [37]
Larry Lauden on the other hand, opines that progress is achieved within a domain when successive theories display increasing problem-solving effectiveness. Laudan sought to invert the logicist view of the relationship between rationality and progress. The logicist view is that development or progresses in science are to be judged by an appeal to a standard of rationality. Laudan’s position, by contrast, is that those developments which are progressive, that is which increase problem-solving effectiveness qualify as rational.[38]
Conclusion
The manner in which science progresses has remained a controversial issue among philosophers of science like Popper, logical empiricists and Kuhn. While Popper and other traditional philosophers of science held that an accumulation or increase in knowledge or truth-likeness of a scientific theory is the indicator for a progressive science, Kuhn on the other hand opines that there can only be progress in science when scientific revolutions occur. He identifies three phases involved in a scientific revolution: the pre-science phase, the normal science phase which is governed by a new paradigm. If the paradigm in a normal science encounters an anomaly which is hard to resolve but rather accumulates to a crisis, a new paradigm might be adopted by the scientific community, and this is the scientific revolution phase. The new paradigm according to Kuhn will be incompatible with the old one and contrary to traditional account. Nearly everyone rejected Kuhnian claims of incommensurability because there was the outrage about its implications for relativism, rationality, objectivity, and progress towards growth.
Bibliography
Books
Bird, Alexander. What is Scientific Progress? Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, inc., 2007.
Chalmers, A. F.  What is This Thing Called Science? Buckingham: Open Uni. Press, 1990.

Dilworth, Craig. Scientific Progress. Netherlands: Springer Publisher, 2007.

Kuhn, Thomas. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: Uni. Of Chicago Press, 1970.

Ladyman, James. Understanding Philosophy of Science. New York: Routledge Publisher, 2002.

Loose, John. A Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. New York: Oxford Uni. Press, 2001.

Journal
Weinberg, S. “The Revolution that Didn’t Happen” The New York Review of Books, (1998), pp. 48-52

Internet Source
Niiniluoto, Ilkka (2011). “Scientific Progress”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2011/entries/scientific-progress/ (4th April 2013).



[1] Cf. A. F. Chalmers, What is This Thing Called Science? (Buckingham: Open Uni. Press, 1990), p. 89.
[2] Cf. Alexander Bird, What is Scientific Progress? (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, inc., 2007), p. 64.
[3] Cf. Craig Dilworth, Scientific Progress (Netherlands: Springer Publisher, 2007), p. 19.
[4] Cf. Ilkka Niiniluoto (2011), “Scientific Progress”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2011/entries/scientific-progress/ (4th April 2013).
[5] Cf. Alexander Bird, loc. cit.
[6] Cf. James Ladyman, Understanding Philosophy of Science (New York: Routledge Publisher, 2002), p. 96.
[7] Cf. A. F. Chalmers, op. cit., p. 90.
[8] Cf. James Ladyman, op. cit., p. 98.
[9] Cf. Ibid., pp. 98-99.
[10] Cf. Ibid. p. 99.
[11] Cf. A. F. Chalmers, op. cit., pp. 90-91.
[12] Cf. Ibid., p. 91.
[13] Ibid.
[14] James Ladyman, op. cit., p. 100
[15] Cf. Ibid., p. 101.
[16] A. F. Chalmers, op. cit., p. 94.
[17] Ibid.
[18] Ibid., p. 96.
[19] Ibid,. p. 97.           
[20] Cf. James Ladyman, op. cit., p. 102.
[21] Cf. Ibid., p. 105.
[22] James Ladyman, op. cit., p. 115.
[23] Cf. Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chicago: Uni. Of Chicago Press, 1970), p. 148.
[24] Cf. Ibid., p. 94
[25] Cf. A. F. Chalmers, op. cit., p. 94.
[26] Cf. James Ladyman, op. cit., p. 116.
[27] Cf. Ibid., p. 97.
[28] Cf. Ibid., p. 98.
[29] Ibid., p.117.
[30] Cf. A. F. Chalmers, op. cit., p. 99.
[31] Cf. Thomas Kuhn, op. cit., p. 168.
[32]  A. F. Chalmers, op. cit., pp. 101-102.
[33] Cf. James Ladyman, op. cit., p. 118.
[34] Ibid.
[35] Ibid.
[36] John Loose, A Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Science (New York: Oxford Uni. Press, 2001), p. 203.
[37] Cf. Ibid.
[38] Cf. Ibid., p.207.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

SUMMARY OF PROVIDENTISSIMUS DEUS, ENCYCLICAL LETTER OF POPE LEO XIII ON THE STUDY OF THE HOLY SCRIPTURE.

summary and appraisal of chapters one, two and three of the book The African Origin of Greek Philosophy: An Exercise in Afrocentrism, by Innocent C. Onyewuenyi.

THE LAST THREE WAYS TO PROVES GOD'S EXISTENCE BY THOMAS AQUINAS