Russell’s idea of mind and matter from his concept of neutral monism.
INTRODUCTION
The questions, “what is man” and “how is he like or
unlike the rest of nature?” have been asked ever since the dawn of
self-consciousness. These questions are formulated and reformulated in every
age. Thus, one major element that has characterized the entire studies in the
discipline known as the Philosophy of Mind has been the mind-body problem. From
the time Plato[1]
asserted that man is not entirely material to this moment, man has been thrown
into a mire of confusion. It is against this backdrop of the solutions
proffered to the mind-body problem that philosophers like Bertrand Russell,
have tried to propound theories that are meant to provide an explanation to
what the mind is or what constitutes it.
The primary intent of this paper is to expose
Russell’s idea of mind and matter from his concept of neutral monism.
According to Russell, what is called mind is a series of events. Thus, mind and
mental are merely approximate concepts. In a complicated science the word mind and matter would both disappear, and would be replaced by causal laws
concerning events.[2]
RUSSELL’S POSITION ON
MIND AND MATTER
Russell rejects the three traditional
principal options in the philosophy of mind, namely: the dualism, materialism
and the idealism. As known, Hobbes being a materialist thinks everything that
exists is ultimately physical. Locke a dualist thinks there are ultimately two
kinds of substance in the universe: mental and physical. And Berkeley, an idealist,
thinks everything that exists is ultimately mental. For Russell, ‘mind’ and
‘matter’ are naive concepts, to be subjected to rigorous philosophical and
scientific criticism. Indeed, Russell believes both idealism and materialism
are inconsistent with the findings of modern science. The universe is not
fundamentally composed of minds or physical objects for Russell, but events.
Events are intrinsically neither mental nor physical, and minds and physical
objects are logical constructions out of those events called the sense data.[3]
Similarly, the concept of mind is logically dependent upon the concept of a
percept, and percepts are events. Indeed, a percept counts as mental only
because a certain knowledge relation called introspection is possible with
regard to it. Events to which a knowledge relation of this sort occurs are
mental, and there can only be percepts if there are items perceived: sense
data, which are in turn events.
NEUTRAL MONISM
In broad historical perspective, neutral
monism is a metaphysical doctrine of the early twentieth century. It was
intended to sub-plant the two traditional and more familiar forms of monistic
doctrine: Idealism, which prescribes a world consisting of minds and their
contents, and Materialism, which sees the identity of everything (persons and
minds included) to consist in configurations of material particles of some
pre-defined type. Although the doctrine is often associated with Russell, its
origin, as Russell himself attested, lies in the work of Ernst Mach (the
nineteenth century Austrian philosopher) and William James, as well as in the
writings before World War I of a group of American philosophers who called
themselves the New Realist.[4]
RUSSELL’S
NEUTRAL MONISM
Russell's doctrine of neutral monism is
not widely known among philosophers. Many who do know something about the
doctrine hardly esteem it, while those commentators who have examined it more
fully rejected over its essential meaning. We must admit that Russell himself
does not provide tremendous help. What we mean here is that, for instance, when
Russell explicitly mentions neutral monism, it is as a particular theory held
by others, such as William James, so that his eventual conversion to it may
give the impression of being merely the acceptance of their views instead of the commencement of a long period
in which he consolidated and developed those views.
Bertrand Russell’s neutral monism sought to dissolve centuries-old disputes
about the nature of mind and matter by denying ontological primacy to both of
them. Reality he claimed is ultimately neither material in nature nor mental.[5] He
tries to construct both the mental world and the physical world out of
components which are in themselves neither mental nor physical but neutral.
Like idealism (the view that there exists nothing but the mental) and
physicalism (the view that there exists nothing but the physical), neutral
monism rejects dualism (the view that there exist distinct mental and physical
substances).[6]
Russell believed mental and physical events to be compresent. Events are compresent when they have at least some shared
spatiotemporal location. Mental and physical event identity is the usual way of
characterizing monism. These two events evidently have identical spatiotemporal
locations so they are compresent. Consequently, Russell asserted that they are
clearly not identical events in any credible sense, even though the same
substance is the subject of the two events. One event essentially involves a
change in temperature while the other does not. Russell questioned, that if these
two events can be compresent without being identical, why cannot mental and
physical events be so? And if they need not be identical, neutral monism is not
established.[7]
In Russell's words, neutral monism maintains that "the things commonly
regarded as mental and the things commonly regarded as physical do not differ
in respect of any intrinsic property possessed by the one set and not by the
other, but differ only in respect of arrangement and context". From its
monistic standpoint, "the whole duality of mind and matter is a mistake.
There is only one kind of stuff out of which the world is made, and this
stuff is called mental in one arrangement, physical in the other"[8]
However, unlike both idealism and
physicalism, neutral monism holds that this single existing substance may be
viewed in some contexts as being mental and in others as being physical. As
Russell puts it,
Neutral
monism as opposed to idealistic monism and materialistic monism, is the theory
that the things commonly regarded as mental and the things commonly regarded as
physical do not differ in respect of any intrinsic property possessed by the
one set and not by the other, but differ only in respect of arrangement and
context.[9]
To help understand this general
suggestion, Russell likened neutral monism’s approach to the double sorting of
names in the (old style) London postal directory, the same names being arranged
alphabetically as well as being listed geographically by their street addresses.
Another simile is that of columns and rows. The very same item can be located
by either its vertical or its horizontal position. It falls within two
different series of items to which it has definably different relations. Since
the item is assumed to occur only within these two series, its identity is
determined by these relations.[10] Another
analogy can be found in the division of the country’s population into groups
living in different areas and its division into the categories used by tax
collectors.[11]
Hence, we can liking the mind and matter like the lion and the unicorn fighting
for the crown; the end of the battle is not the victory of one or the other,
but the discovery that both are only heraldic inventions. The aim of the
neutral monism is to show that the difference between the physical and the
mental is not a difference of components but only a difference in the way in
which the components are put together.
SENSE
DATA AND THE PROBLEM OF MATTER
An interest in questions of what we can
know about the world, about objects or matter is a theme that begins to colour
Russell’s work. In 1912 Russell asks whether there is anything that is beyond
doubt. His investigation implies a particular view of what exists, based on
what it is we can believe with greatest certainty.
Acknowledging that visible properties, like colour,
are variable from person to person as well as within one person’s experience
and are a function of light’s interaction with our visual apparatus (eyes, and
so forth). Russell concludes that we do not directly experience what we would
normally describe as coloured or more broadly, visible objects. Rather, we
infer the existence of such objects from what we are directly
acquainted with, namely, our sense experiences. The same holds for other
sense-modalities, and the sorts of objects that we would normally describe as
audible, scented, and so forth. For instance, in seeing and smelling a flower,
we are not directly acquainted with a flower, but with the sense-data
of colour, shape, aroma, and so on. These sense-data are what are immediately
and certainly known in sensation, while material objects (like the
flower) that we normally think of as producing these experiences via the
properties they bear (colour, shape, aroma) are merely inferred.
These epistemological doctrines have latent
metaphysical implications: because they are inferred rather than known
directly, ordinary sense objects (like flowers) have the status of hypothetical
or theoretical entities, and therefore may not exist. And since many ordinary
sense objects are material, this calls the nature and existence of matter into
question. Like Berkeley,
Russell thinks it is possible that what we call “the material world” may be
constructed out of elements of experience, not ideas, as Berkeley thought, but
sense-data. That is, sense-data may be the ultimate reality. Although Russell
thought this was possible, he did not at this time embrace such a view.
Instead, he continued to think of material objects as real, but as known only
indirectly, via inferences from sense-data. This type of view is sometimes
called “indirect realism.”
Although Russell is at this point willing to doubt the
existence of physical objects and replace them with inferences from sense-data,
he is unwilling to doubt the existence of universals, since even sense-data
seem to have sharable properties. Russell argues, that aside the sense data and
inferred physical objects, there must also be qualities and relations (that is,
universals). Since in “I am in my room,” the word “in” has meaning and denotes
something real, namely, a relation between me and my room.[12]
RELATIONSHIP
BETWEEN MIND AND MATTER
The problem of the relationship of mental
and physical aspects of reality has long been a key one, especially in Western
philosophy. Descartes gave a particularly clear formulation of the essential
difficulties when he considered matter as extended substance (spatiotemporal)
while mind was regarded as thinking substance (immaterial). He pointed
out that, in mind, there can be clear and distinct thoughts that correspond in
content to distinct objects that are separated in space. But these thoughts are
not in themselves actually located in separate regions of space, nor do they
seem to be anything like separate material objects.
It appears that the natures of mind and
matter are so different that one can see no basis for a relationship between
them. This point was put very clearly by Descartes[13]
when he said that there is nothing included in the concept of body that belongs
to mind, and nothing in that of mind that belongs to body. Yet, experience
shows that they are closely related. Descartes solved the problem by assuming
that God, who created both mind and matter, is able to relate them by putting
into the minds of human beings the clear and distinct thoughts that are needed
to deal with matter as extended substance. It was also implied by Descartes
that the aims contained in thoughts had somehow to be carried out by the body,
even though he asserted that thought and the body had no domain in common.[14]
It would seem that nothing is left but to appeal to God to arrange the desired
action. However, since that time, such an appeal to the action of God has
generally ceased to be accepted as a valid philosophical argument. But this
leaves us with no explanation of how mind and matter are related.
A CRITIC OF RUSSELL’S THEORY OF NEUTRAL
MONISM
Russell’s
theory of “neutral stuff” differs from both that of William James and the
American neo-realists. James included what Russell calls sensations. According
to a purely neutral monistic theory of the world there is nothing either in
mind or in matter which is not wholly constructed out of the neutral stuff.
Russell departs from this formula in two respects. In the first place, although
sensation, which is the neutral stuff, is the most important component of mind,
it is not the only component.
Consequently,
mental phenomena are not reduced to sensations, but to sensations and images.
Thus, images are not part of neutral stuff. They are never found in the
physical and are purely subjective.[15]
In a pure neutral monism, there should be nothing which is purely subjective.
However, it is true that images are like sensations and may be derived from
them. However, as being found solely in the realm of the mind, they constitute
a departure from neutral monism. On the other hand, it is doubtful whether in
Russell’s theory, matter can be said to be composed solely of the neutral stuff
of sensation.
Neutral-monist theories have equally been
criticized as inadequate in their account of either mind or body. For Hume, his
concept of mind as a bundle of perceptions, inadequately accounts for the
identity and simplicity of the mind. Others have criticized the notion that
physical bodies comprise some sort of primary experience as implicitly
idealistic. Hence, the central problem for neutral monism is seen as that of
specifying clearly the nature of the neutral stuff without qualifying it in an
exclusively mental or physical fashion.
CONCLUSION
Through centuries, the
discourse on mind and matter in the philosophy of mind has remained a very
controversial one. It however, seems almost impossible to arrive at a
conclusive end to the question of “what is mind?” Among other philosophical
position, Russell neutral monism informs us that, matter as an entity does not
exist, what has been regarded as matter up till now is in fact event. Thus
the aim of the neutral monism is to show that the difference between the
physical and the mental is not a difference of components but only a difference
in the way in which the components are put together. Matter
therefore, is a mental construction, a postulate made to explain events.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Bohm,
David. 'A New Theory of the Relationship
of Mind and Matter', Philosophical Psychology. United kingdom: Birkbeck
College, 1990.
Carey, Rosalind (2008), “Russell’s Metaphysics”, Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
James Fieser & Bradley Dowden (Ed.). URL = http://www.iep.utm.edu/russ-met/#SH3g
Irvine A. D.
(2012), "Bertrand Russell", The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, Edward N. Zalta (Ed.), URL =
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/russell (4 Nov. 2012)
Lowe, Jonathan. An
Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind. United Kingdom: Cambridge
University Press, 2000.
Omoregbe, Joseph. Philosophy of Mind: An Introduction To
Philosophical Psychology. Lagos: Joja Press Ltd., 2001.
Priest, Stephen. The British Empiricists. USA:
Routledge, 2007
Robert Tully, Russell’s Neutral Monism.
http//digitalcommons.msmaster.ca/cgi/veiwcontent
Thomas Knierim, Mind and
Consciousness – http://www.thebigview.com (3 Jan. 2013)
Russell, Bertrand.
My Philosophical Development. New
York: Reehl Litho Co., 1959
Stace W. T.,
“Russell’s Neutral Monism” The Philosophy
of Bertrand Russell, edited by Paul Schilpp. USA: Harper & Row
Publishers, 1963, pp. 361-362
Tully, Robert.
"Russell’s Neutral Monism" The Cambridge Companion to Bertrand Russel, edited by
Nicholas Griffin. USA: Cambridge University Press, 2003, pp. 332 - 370
[1] Plato, in his theory of Forms suggests that
(1) the world of Forms is separate from the world of perceptible objects (the two-world view),
(2) perceptible objects are images or copies of the Forms and (3)
perceptible objects are unreal or “less real” than the Forms.
[2] Joseph Omoregbe, Philosophy of Mind: An Introduction To Philosophical Psychology
(Lagos: Joja Press Ltd., 2001), p. 19
[3] Stephen Priest, The British Empiricists (USA: Routledge,
2007), pp. 220 - 221
[4] Robert Tully,
"Russell’s Neutral Monism." In The Cambridge Companion to Bertrand Russell. Ed. Nicholas Griffin, (USA: Cambridge
University Press, 2003), p. 335
[5] Robert Tully, "Russell’s Neutral Monism."
In The Cambridge
Companion to Bertrand Russell.
Ed. Nicholas Griffin, (USA: Cambridge University Press, 2003), p. 335.
[6] A. D. Irvine (2012), "Bertrand
Russell", In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Edward N.
Zalta (ed.), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/russell
(4 Nov. 2012)
[7] Stephen Priest, The British Empiricists (USA: Routledge,
2007), pp. 225
[8] Robert Tully, Russell’s
Neutral Monism. pp 209 - 211
http//digitalcommons.msmaster.ca/cgi/veiwcontent
[9] A. D. Irvine (2012),
"Bertrand Russell" In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL =
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/russell (4 Nov. 2012)
[10] Robert Tully,
"Russell’s Neutral Monism." In The Cambridge Companion to Bertrand Russell. Ed. Nicholas Griffin, (USA: Cambridge
University Press, 2003), p. 336
[11] A. D. Irvine (2012), "Bertrand
Russell" In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Edward N.
Zalta (ed.), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/russell
(13 Nov. 2012)
[12] Rosalind
Carey (2008), “Russell’s Metaphysics” In Internet
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, James Fieser & Bradley Dowden (Ed.). URL= http://www.iep.utm.edu/russ-met/#SH3g
[13] David
Bohm (1990) 'A new theory of the relationship of mind and matter',
Philosophical Psychology, (United kingdom: Birkbeck College, 1990), p. 271
[14] David Bohm (1990), p. 272
[15] Cf. Stace W. T.,
“Russell’s Neutral Monism.” In The
Philosophy of Bertrand Russell, Ed. Paul Schilpp (USA: Harper & Row
Publishers, 1963), pp. 361-362
Comments
Post a Comment