SUMMARY OF EPISTEMOLOGY
WHAT IS JUSTIFICATION AND
WHY DOES IT MATTER IN EPISTEMOLOGY? DISCUSS ANY THREE THEORIES OF EPISTEMIC
JUSTIFICATION, SHOWING HOW RELEVANT THEY MIGHT BE TO IDEAL LIFE-SITUATION.
The
theory of justification is a part of epistemology that attempts to understand
the justification of propositions and beliefs. Epistemologists are concerned
with various epistemic features of belief, which includes the ideas of
justification, warrant, rationality, and probability. Justification, according
to the tripartite theory of knowledge, is the difference between merely
believing something that is true, and knowing it. To have knowledge, on this
account, we must have justification, and to have justification about our belief
is to have good reasons to think that they are true. Therefore, justification
has been considered being epistemologically important properly for a claim to
count as knowledge claim. It is one that is important in our evaluation of our
beliefs qua beliefs, a methodic speech act wherein the epistemist offers
reasons in defense of one’s propositional attitudes, that is, of one’s beliefs
and conclusions. However, how beliefs are justified is among the central
questions of epistemology. Justification could also be done in repudiation of a
given claim. In this case, the epistemologist tends to distinguish
deontological and non-deontological justification.
Deontological Justification: This has to do with offering reasons in defense of one’s knowledge
claims, purely out of a sense of epistemic duty, in other words, justificatory
activity is purely perfunctory.
The
deontological understanding of the concept of justification is common to the
way philosophers such as Descartes, Locke, Moore and Chisholm have thought
about justification. Today, however, the dominant view is that the
deontological understanding of justification is unsuitable for the purpose of
epistemology since for some, deontological justification presupposes that we can have a sufficiently high
degree of control over our beliefs. But beliefs are not akin; they simply arise
in or happen to us. Therefore, beliefs are not suitable for deontological
evaluation. The other reason is that deontological justification does not tend
to ‘epistemize’ true beliefs: it does not tend to make them non-accidentally
true. Deontological justification could be represented as follows:
I.
S
is justified in believing that p, iff
II.
S
believes that p
III.
S
is obliged not to refrain from believing p.
Non-deontological
Justification: This claims that probabilification and deontological
justification can diverge: it is possible for a belief to be deontologically
justified without being properly probabilified. So, for a belief to be
justified, it has to instantiate the property of proper probalilification. It
can be represented logically as
I.
S is justified in
believing that p, iff
II.
S believes that p
III.
S believes that p in a
properly probabilified manner.
As
an epistemic process, justification is done in fidelity to the standard of
philosophical discourse, otherwise, it fails to be a case of justification
hence reasonableness remains the yardstick for justification. However, although
it is true that one cannot proffer indefeasible reasons to the skeptics in
order to justify one’s claims, one has to be modest as dubitability,
corrigibility and fallibility will always be present in a bid to justify our
knowledge claims. Following the
tripartite account of knowledge, justification being very important in the
knowledge process, has to be methodic, well thought out, and well articulated.
To justify our claims, we have to be systematic, coherent, compelling,
consistent and convincing. But that does not mean that we should not be modest
with regards to the incorrigibility and indefeasibility of our claims.
Why does justification
matter in epistemology?
William
Alston had claimed that justification is of no epistemic importance. Alston in
the work: “Concepts of Epistemic Justification (1985) argues for the importance
and superiority of reliabilist warrant over and above justification. Alston’s
argument is that one is more likely to attain truth by believing the warranted
proposition than the justified propositions; since beliefs that could be
reached by a method that is in fact reliable is likely to be true. For him, truth-conduciveness
should be the standard for evaluating beliefs. Contrary to this view, Matthew
Weiner, in his work: “Why Does Justification Matters” (2005), argues that Justification
is an important epistemic property. For him, the criterion for epistemological
importance is effectiveness and knowability. This views claims that
epistemological importance, contrary to the claims of some scholars, does not
only require truth-conduciveness, as measured by effectiveness, but also
dependence on experience, as measured by knowability.
Weiner
posited that being justified on this completely experience-dependence
conception of justification makes a belief good from the epistemic point of view;
hence, justification is epistemologically important. Weiner also argues that
Alston’s proposal makes warrant more effective property than justification but
for Weiner, to make effectiveness the sole criterion of epistemological
importance would make truth the only epistemologically important propositional
property.
Weiner
argues that the importance of effectiveness and knowability averts the collapse
of positive epistemic status to truth. Truth is not the only epistemologically
important property, because truth is not completely knowable. Warrant is
superior to justification with respect to effectiveness, but inferior with
respect to knowability.
Weiner
thus ascertains that, if one succeeds in believing what is warranted, one would
be more likely to attain the truth than if one believes what is justified. But
believing what is justified, however, requires no information other than what one’s
experience has made available, while believing what is warranted will require
guess work. It is this complete experience-dependence, he concludes, that makes
justification epistemologically important.
Another
reason why justification matters in epistemology is that it helps to
distinguish between knowledge and mere belief; as the third condition in the
tripartite account of knowledge, justification serves as an intermediary
between doxa (option) and epistemic (knowledge). Certainly, an
opinion remains an intangible claim unless it is justified. In a similar
fashion, justification ensures certainty in our claims to knowledge. it is that
epistemic property that qualifies any potential candidate (beliefs/ claims) as
knowledge.
Justification
also helps to distinguish lucky guess and fact. Here, though it’s properly
experience-dependent, justification provides us with facts to strengthen our
arguments as against lucky guess. In all, justification distinguishes between
reasonable and possible doubts, where reasonableness is the yardstick for
justification. In other words, reason (rather than uncalled doubts) should be
the ultimate court of appeal where our claims are to be justified.
Theories of justification
Foundationalism:
this is the position that all beliefs are of two kinds: basic beliefs which are
self justifying and non-basic beliefs that needs to be justified by their
inferential relationship to the basic beliefs. Foundationalism as a theory of
justification posits that some beliefs are incorrigible and infallible, hence
do not need to be justified; these beliefs are said to be self-evident or
derived from intuitions. The claim that some beliefs are infallible and
self-evident is fundamental to the argument of the fundamentalists. They argue
further that other beliefs, that is the non-basic beliefs, can only be
justified, if and only if they are inferentially related to the self evident
ones which they call the fundamental beliefs.
The
most popular example of the foundationalist theory is the view expressed by
Rene Descartes. In fact, Descartes introduced the architectonic image of
foundationalism by affirming the need for a deconstruction of epistemic
superstructures until one gets to a solid base upon which one can erect other
forms of epistemic beliefs. Obviously, his “basic belief” is evident in his
famous dictum cogito ego sum while
other beliefs which are derived inferentially form it are non-basic beliefs.
Similarly,
the position of the foundationalists is basically that any belief can either be
justified if it is self-evident such as: “I think therefore I am” or 2+2 = 4,
while other beliefs which are not self-evident are justified by their
relationship to the basic ones. E.g, two mangoes and another two mangoes will
be four mangoes can be derived from the self-evident basic belief of 2+2=4.
This
way of conceiving beliefs by the foundationalists has created an architectural
model in the minds of people. The foundationalist drawing inspiration from the
Cartesian metaphor conceives beliefs as a superstructure with the basic beliefs
serving as the foundation, while non-basic beliefs represent the structure
itself. Like a good architecture, to continue with the metaphor, the
foundationalists beliefs that the survival of the non-basic beliefs rests on
the support supplied by the foundational beliefs, just as the survival of an
edifice rest on the strength of the base. In essence, the justification of
non-basic beliefs depends on the strength of the basic beliefs.
Criticism
It
has been argued that the incorrigibility factor is the Achilles’ heel of
foundationalism. The attempt to maintain that some beliefs are self-evident and
infallible has raised questions such as: what do they mean by an infallible
belief? Do we have certain beliefs that do not need any justification?
Another
serious criticism against the foundationalists is the point that
foundationalist, in terminating the regress of justification, do so
arbitrarily. Furthermore, foundationalists have been criticized of conceiving
beliefs as linearly and hierarchically arranged. The claim here is that
beliefs, as against the foundationalists, are not developed in a constructive
manner which can make us talk of a linear or hierarchical order of epistemic
chains.
One
the whole, in order that the demise of foundationalism should not be announced,
modesty should be introduced in our knowledge claims such that some forms of
defeasibility could be welcomed.
Coherentism:
Coherentism is from the verb “cohere”, this word is cognate with verbs as
“adhere”. To cohere means to stick together. Coherenticism, as an alternative
to foundationalism, holds that a belief is justified or justifiably held, if it
coheres with a set of beliefs, and by this they reject the notion of any foundational
belief. So, knowledge and justified belief does not in any way rest on a
foundation of non-inferential justified beliefs. Beliefs are justified,
therefore, to the extent they cohere with other beliefs in a given system of
beliefs. The better our belief fit into our already existing system of beliefs,
the better that belief is justified, and this reduces justification to a
question of relationship. The most obvious weakness in this view is the failure
on their part to account for the things that must cohere in order for a given
belief to be justified, and the relationship that must hold among these things
in order for the belief in question to be justified.
Contextualism: This
view claims that whatever we know is in a context. Context here is seen in
relation to certain features, such as intentions and presupposition of members
of a conversational situation. These features determine under what standards
one’s claims are taken to count as knowledge. However, this theory does not
support the objectivity of knowledge, since one context differs from another,
and the presupposition of members of a conversation implies relativising
knowledge, since they accept that standard of justification varies from context
to context.
Michael
Williams while taking epistemological contextualism to a more prominent form
rejects skepticism as unnatural, since it is dependent on essentially
contentious ideas and being theoretical, it cannot be forced on our ordinary
way of epistemic thinking. He argued that, independent of any situational,
disciplinary, and other contextually variable factors, a proposition has no
epistemic status whatsoever. There is no fact of the matter as to what kind of
justification it either admits or requires. David Annis, on his part, pointed
out that foundationalism and coherentism both ignore the social nature of
justification. For him, a subject is justified to hold knowledge of an object,
if the subject can meet certain objections that express doubt.
Despite
all these arguments, it appears that contextualism has failed to satisfactorily
explain “how”, not “why” we can be puzzled by the epistemic puzzles of the
skeptics. Their arguments, rather, imply that when we make epistemic claims
within a context, we systematically confound our claims to what we will claim
in some other contexts. This, Steven Schiffer says, is not true, because it
means that the claimant is ignorant of the context of his epistemic claim. In
such a case, Schiffer argues that the contextualist’s solution has not also
satisfactorily explained what he set out to explain. Whether Schiffer’s
assessment is true is open to debate, but suffice it to say that from our
discussions so far, the skeptical challenge to justification seems to have no
adequate response, such that even contemporary western epistemology still
battles with providing a refutation of various forms to skepticism. This is
confirmed by the popular saying that all the problems of the theory of knowledge,
even the more general ones, have their roots in the belief that knowledge is
impossible or at least, not certain; an attitude of a typical skeptic.
DISCUSS THE GETTIER
PROBLEM, AND ATTEMPT A PHILOSOPHICAL CRITIQUE OF THE COUNTER-EXAMPLES PRESENTED
IN EDMUND GETTIER’S “IS JUSTIFIED TRUE BELIEF KNOWLEDGE?” (1964)
Edmund
Gettier’s problem consists in his epistemic concern regarding what conditions
are individually necessary and collectively sufficient for a claim to count as
epistemic one. Thus, the expression “Gettier problem” refers to a problem in
modern epistemology or first-order logic, issuing from counter-examples to the
definition of knowledge as “Justified True Belief” (JTB), dealing extensively
with the concept of JTB, thr scope of the concept as well as thr attacks upon
JTB which Gettier’s examples introduce.
In
opposition to the criteria for knowledge found in the Theatetus’ tripartite account of knowledge as “Justified True
Belief”, Edmund Gettier in his article “Is
Justified True Belief Knowledge? (1964)” offered counter examples to the three
criteria proposed in the Theatetus in a bid to show that justified true belief is not
sufficient for one’s having knowledge hence the need for the fourth criteria.
He painted systematic scenarios whereby beliefs were both true and justified, but for
reasons unrelated to the justification. The problematic for Gettier therefore
is: since such beliefs are not based on the right kind of justification, should
we intuitively claim to have knowledge of such?
For
Gettier, while justified belief in a proposition is a necessary condition for
knowing, it is not sufficient. In fact, in some circumstance, even when all
traditional conditions for knowledge are met, one might still fail to have
knowledge. Thus, it is possible to mistake as knowledge, a true belief whose
justification is based on epistemic guess or luck, rather than good evidence.
Such would then constitute a defective justification of a true belief. There is
therefore need for the fourth condition which would render any form of
Gettierization impossible.
Philosophical critique of
the counter-examples
As
J. T. Ekong intimated in his article “ A Critique of Edmund Gettier’s Account
of Knowledge”, responses to Gettier’s counter-examples can be grouped into
three (3): the first group are those who attempts to offer a fourth condition
for knowledge, the second group are those who attempt to strengthen the
traditional JTB account of knowledge such that it becomes Gettier-resistant or
undefeated by Gettier’s counter-examples, and finally, the third group are
those who considers the entire argument of Gettier as defective, on the grounds
that they rely on a false principle namely: That false proposition can justify
one’s belief in another proposition. Thus, the falsity of the principle on
which the counter-examples depends, they said, invariably entails the falsity
of the counter-examples.
The
reliabilist, Alvin Goldman and Richard Kirkham belongs to the first group. He
proposes infallibilism as a fourth condition. He argues that the only
definition of knowledge that could ever be immune to all counter-examples is
the infallibilists one. Hence, for a belief to be considered as knowledge, it
must not only be true and justified, but this justification of the belief must
necessitate its truth, the justification for the belief must also be
infallible. Another fourth condition proposed is indefeasibility wherein
proponents of this argues that there should be no overriders or defeasible
conditions to the reasons that justify one’s belief if such beliefs must count
as knowledge.
Proponents
of the second group include the likes of Henri Poincare and L. E. J Brouwer.
For them, given that attempts to offer a viable fourth condition as required by
Gettier has been very thorny, it appears what the Gettier problem wants is not
a fourth condition rather, the JTB needs a formalized reconstruction. They
often call into question the law of excluded middle (a thing either is or is
not), by this, they argue that a justified true belief either constitutes
knowledge or does not. So the definition of knowledge must set it apart from
that which does not constitute knowledge. The JTB account must then be revised
in such a way that it can account for what stands for knowledge, without having
to seek additional conditions to make it pass the scrutiny of critics.
D.
M Armstrong, John Pollock, and Richard Feldman belongs to the last group. in
his work: “An Alleged Defect in Gettier Counter-Examples”, Feldman argues that
we cannot fault Gettier’s counter-examples, since for him, they rely on the
allegedly false principles; that false propositions can justify one’s belief in
other propositions. Armstrong in his part posits that Gettiers argument is
based on a false ground that is too weak to serve as suitable grounds.
WRITE SHORT NOTES ON:
VIRTUE EPISTEMOLOGY, RELIGIOUS EPISTEMOLOGY, SOCIAL EPISTEMOLOGY, NATURALIZED
EPISTEMOLOGY, FEMINIST EPISTEMOLOGY, AND MORAL EPISTEMOLOGY.
Virtue Epistemology
Virtue is a version of epistemology
which argues that rather than focus on the subject’s beliefs, its justification
and how one’s belief can translate to knowledge, a preoccupation of traditional
epistemology, rather, we should analyze the epistemic virtues and vices of the
subject. It is in determining which way of forming belief that is epistemic
virtue and which is epistemic vice that we can determine the epistemic quality
of a particular belief.
Virtue epistemology is committed to
firstly, the claim that epistemology is normative in character, and secondly,
they claim and take intellectual agents and communities to be the primary
sources of epistemic values and primary focus of epistemic evaluation. Virtue
epistemologists can be divided into two groups. Virtue reliabilists conceive of intellectual virtues as
stable and reliable cognitive faculties or powers and cite vision,
introspection, memory, and the like as paradigm cases of intellectual virtue.
These virtue epistemologists tend to focus on formulating virtue-based accounts
of knowledge or justification.
Virtue responsibilists
conceive of intellectual virtues as good intellectual character traits, traits
like attentiveness, fair-mindedness, open-mindedness, intellectual tenacity, and
courage. While some virtue responsibilists have also attempted to give
virtue-based accounts of knowledge or justification, others have pursued less
traditional projects, focusing on such issues as the nature and value of
virtuous intellectual character as such, the relation between intellectual
virtue and epistemic responsibility, and the relevance of intellectual virtue
to the social and cross-temporal aspects of the intellectual life.
Ernest Sosa introduced the notion of
an intellectual virtue into contemporary epistemological discussion in a 1980
paper, “The Raft and the Pyramid.” Sosa argued in this paper that an appeal to
intellectual virtue could resolve the conflict between foundationalists and
coherentists over the structure of epistemic justification. One of the major
proponents of virtue epistemology is Duncan Pritchard.
Religious Epistemology
Religious
Epistemology is the branch of epistemology which
questions religious beliefs and propositions in a bid to know whether they are
rational, justified, warranted, reasonable, based on evidence and so on.
It is therefore a broad label which covers any approach to epistemological questions from a religious perspective, or attempts to understand
the epistemological issues that come from religious belief.
It questions the possibility of attaining a rational foundation of faith or
attaining knowledge of God and how we can attain knowledge of God, if he
exists. It seeks to know whether or not God can be perceptible, or is h known
only through mystical experience. Religious epistemology also attempts to know
if, given the existence of evil in the world which many have used to argue
against the possible existence of God, if based on the evidence given, we can
lusciously posit the non-existence of God. Some of the proponents of Religious
Epistemology include Alvin Plantinga, Willaim Alston and the likes.
Social Epistemology
Social epistemology refers to a broad set of approaches to the study of knowledge
that construes human knowledge as a collective achievement. Another way of
characterizing social epistemology is as the study of the social dimensions of
knowledge.
There is little consensus, however, on what the term "knowledge"
comprehends, what is the scope of the "social", or what the style or
purpose of the study should be. The
term "social epistemology" was first used by the library scientists Margaret Egan and Jesse Shera in the 1950s
Social Epistemology, as a field within analytic philosophy,
foregrounds the social aspects of knowledge in the creation and dissemination
knowledge. What precisely these social aspects are, and whether they have beneficial
or detrimental effects on the possibilities to create, acquire and spread
knowledge is a subject of continuous debate within the ambience of epistemology.
Within the field, “the social” is approached in two complementary and not
mutually exclusive ways: firstly, the social character of knowledge can either
be approached through inquiries in inter-individual epistemic relations or through
inquiries focusing on epistemic communities.
The inter-individual approach typically focuses on issues
such as testimony,
epistemic trust as a form of trust placed by one individual in another,
epistemic dependence, and epistemic authority. The community approach typically
focuses on issues such as community standards of justification, community
procedures of critique, diversity, epistemic justice, and collective knowledge.
As a field within Analytic philosophy, Social Epistemology has close ties with,
and often overlaps with Feminist Epistemology and Philosophy of Science. While parts of the field engage in abstract, normative
considerations of knowledge creation and dissemination, other parts of the
field are naturalized epistemology in the sense that they draw on empirically
gained insights.
The Major proponents of Social epistemology are Alvin Goldman and Steve Fuller.
Naturalized Epistemology
There is not generally acceptable
definition of Naturalized Epistemology even among different Naturalists. C. B.
Wreen explains that this is not only because of the dispute on the kind of
empirical sciences they consider as relevant to epistemological questions, but
also because of the kind of question it should ask, and the degree to which
epistemology should employ empirical sciences and so on. A narrow view of
naturalized epistemology defines it as a theory that employs empirical science
in epistemological theories. This view is not an adequate way of explaining the
details of this domain, since it places naturalism in one category without
distinction. But Richard Feldman defines naturalized
epistemology as an attempt to make epistemology closely related to the natural
science. Feldman went ahead to divide naturalized epistemology into three broad groups: the
replacement naturalism, the substantive naturalism, and the co-operative
naturalism, with all types differing in the way they interpret the relationship
between the empirical sciences and epistemology.
I.
Replacement naturalism
aims at discovering the relation between our theories and their evidence. It
eliminates any need for conceptual analysis. They reject traditional
epistemology, arguing that the epistemological project show employ the methods
of the natural science if it must record progress. The major proponent of this
group is W. V. O Quine. In his work; “Epistemology Naturalized” (1968), Quine attempts
to make epistemology a chapter of psychology since for him, there is no
demarcation between empirical science and epistemology. Both have the same
aims, tackle the same questions, and employ the same methods.
II.
Substantive naturalism
argues for
a combination of the tools of traditional epistemology with the tools of the
empirical sciences. This group applies empirical
science, theories, and methods of cognitive psychology, in pursuing
epistemology. Prominent
in this group is Alvin Goldman.
III.
Cooperative naturalism is an
overlap between cooperative naturalism and substantive naturalism. This group argues that empirical
results of psychology are necessary in answering the evaluative questions
pursued by epistemology. Thus, they view epistemological progress (especially
in answering epistemic and evaluative questions) as one which is dependent on
the input of the empirical sciences. Amirah Albahri, further categorized this
group into: Strategic Reliabilism, Pragmatism, and Natural kind theory.
In general, Theories of cooperative naturalism argue
for empirical science to be the starting point for epistemological
investigation. For them, the methods and theories of empirical science can help
answer epistemological questions. Prominent in this group is C. S. Stich and Hillary
Kornblith.
Feminist Epistemology
Feminist
epistemology studies the ways in which gender does and ought to influence our
conceptions of knowledge, the knowing subject, and practices of inquiry and
justification. It identifies ways in which dominant conceptions and practices
of knowledge attribution, acquisition, and justification systematically
disadvantage women and other subordinated groups, and strives to reform these
conceptions and practices so that they serve the interests of these groups.
Furthermore, feminist epistemology aims at explaining why and how entry of
female researches into sciences (particularly biological and social sciences)
has generated new questions, theories, and methods showing how gender has in
fact played a causal role in these transformations “defending these changes as
cognitive, not just social, advances”
What is common to feminist epistemologies is an emphasis on
the epistemic salience of gender and the use of gender as an analytic category
in discussions, criticisms, and reconstructions of epistemic practices, norms,
and ideals. While feminist epistemology is not easily and simply characterized,
feminist approaches to epistemology tend to share an emphasis on the ways in
which knowers are particular and concrete, rather than abstract and
universalizable. Feminist epistemologies take seriously the ways in which
knowers are enmeshed in social relations that are generally hierarchical while
also being historically and culturally specific. In addition, feminist
epistemologies assume that the ways in which knowers are constituted as
particular subjects are significant to epistemological problems such as
warrant, evidence, justification, and theory-construction, as well as to our
understanding of terms like “objectivity,” “rationality,” and “knowledge.”
Susan Bordo in the work: The Flight to Objectivity:
Essays on Cartesianism and Culture (1990) and Genevieve Lloyd in her work: The
Man of Reason: “Male” and “Female” in Western Philosophy (1984) tried to
analyze the ways in which metaphors of masculinity operate in constructions of
ideals of rationality and objectivity and of the role of the symbolic imaginary
and metaphor in modern epistemological projects, both Lloyd and Bordo argues
that the operations of the symbolic imaginary are implicated in the metaphysics
of subjectivity and objectivity and in the characterization of epistemic
problems that follow from that metaphysics. The result of the work done by
these feminist historians is that ideals of reason, objectivity, autonomy, and
disinterestedness operating in assumptions about inquiry, as well as the idea
that the “perennial” problems of epistemology are gender neutral are now
revealed to be connected to and constitutive of gender relations.
Moral Epistemology
Moral epistemology is the study of moral knowledge and related phenomena.
Historically, this branch of epistemology could be traceable to Socrates’
inquiries into whether virtue and expertise in governance can be taught. Moral
epistemology seeks to determine whether any of our moral judgments count as
knowledge and to provide an account of whatever moral knowledge we do have.
Unfortunately this traditional understanding puts moral epistemology at risk of
being a field with which many ethical theorists can have no substantial
engagement.
Moral
epistemology questions the possibility of moral knowledge. Since the basic
moral categories are those of right and wrong action, moral epistemology
questions how we can arrive at the knowledge of which action is right and which
is wrong.
CRITICALLY DISCUSS THE
NOTION OF “EPISTEMOLOGICAL FORCING” AS A TRENDY WAY OF CONFRONTING THE
CHALLENGE OF SKEPTICISM, AND ACCOUNT FOR ITS PLAUSIBILITY OR IMPLAUSIBILITY AS
A PHILOSOPHICAL METHOD OF DISPUTATION
Literature
has it that Skepticism has, for centuries, proven to be the “gadfly” to
epistemic dogmatism, since by being reluctant to accepting anything at
face-value, the skeptic wants to lead epistemists to the awareness of the
epistemic plight of possible error even at the face of evidence for our
knowledge claims. It calls for a justification of the justification for our
knowledge, but this will lead the epistemist to commit the fallacy of
begging-the-question. To the dismay of all, attempts to escape the challenge of
skepticism have proven abortive, despite all the divergent theories which have
been expunged to shut the skeptic. Consequent upon this, skepticism presents
itself as a major limiting factor and challenge to epistemological accomplishment.
Among
such attempts is the view that the skeptic question, just like any other rude
question should be answered with silence, others appeal to Fallibilism about
certainty, still others employs the principle of closure of justification. Despite
these attempts, the skeptics still wear their garment of knowledge vacuity,
claiming that knowledge faculty is cognitively vacuous, and as such, knowledge
is unachievable. However, it seems the argument-by-argument technique will
continue to yield less. This led to the emergence of the principle of
“epistemological forcing” which presents itself as a better candidate to
confront the challenge of skepticism. Our aim therefore shall be to critically
examine this principle.
Epistemic
forcing is a technique of constraining skeptical maneuvers within an appropriate
range of situations; it is a trendy way of confronting the skeptics. The
heuristic principle of forcing is this: whenever knowledge claims are
challenged by the alleged possibility of error, the strategy is to shoe that
the possibilities of error fail to be genuine in the relevant sense. Here, one
could also appeal to certain pre-philosophical intuitions, or spontaneous
convictions that the skeptic holds unquestioned, and without which it would be
extremely difficult to embark on any rational enquiry.
This
technique is based on the principle of reasonableness of doubt, such that
doubts which are reasonable will have the epistemic warrant to be answered,
while doubts which are unreasonable do not. The technique emphasizes two
things: cognitive limits, and the limit of reasonableness of doubts. With this
they mean that when the bonds of reasonableness are violated, skeptical demands
lose their initial force and legitimacy.
The Plausibility of this technique
as a philosophical method of disputation
This
technique, as a philosophical method of disputation, is very plausible,
reasonable and reliable to thrive in its aim of confronting the challenge of
skepticism. Firstly, epistemological forcing uses the modest version of
foundationalism in its quest to limit the range of possibilities within which
the skeptical challenge can achieve success.
The moderate version of foundationalism does
not make absolute or exalted claims like the classical foundationalism even
though it makes claims to certainty in epistemic justification, such claims is
not construed to a definitive, fallible or non-revisable sense, rather, this
model accommodates the concerns of epistemic anxieties of the
anti-foundationalist including such as the skeptic and the falliblists, by
characterizing the foundations of knowledge and justification in a manner that
is of interest and relevance to them. It acknowledges both the certainty and
fragility of our foundations upon which human knowledge and its justification
rest.
The
technique emphasizes cognitive limits as well as the limit of reasonableness of
doubts. With this they mean that when the bonds of reasonableness are violated,
skeptical demands lose their initial force and legitimacy. Therefore, with this
principle, the skeptical challenge, even if not completely refuted, can at
least be minimized.
This
principle makes it known to the skeptic that error is accidental not essential
to the human mind. This is explained by the fact that human mind can detect and
correct its own errors of judgment, which shows that human reason is neither
constitutionally incapable of knowing truth with certitude, nor congenitally
unable to detect, admit and correct its mistakes in the process of cognition. If
this were so, we will not be able to alter our views when we err, and even of
discovering and recognizing truth.
The
argument-by-argument approach to the skeptical challenge smacks of a
“justificationist addiction”, a method which provides a huge failure for the
classical foundationalists, and has scarcely any prospects of success in our
time. The classical foundationalism made claims to strong justification,
epistemic corrigibility and indubitability. But it fails to satisfy that
standard it set and that is why it crumbled. It simply could not provide
non-question-begging guarantees for the robust claims it made.
Relevance of this
principle to real life situation
This
strategy has implications for the principle of reasonable doubts in
jurisprudence. A reasonable doubt is a doubt that is based on reason and common
sense, the kind of doubt that would make a reasonable person hesitate to act.
In the law court, the judge would only pass a judgment when evidence has been
given beyond any reasonable doubt.
In
the same way, to justify or prove epistemic claims beyond reasonable doubts of
the skeptic means providing them in such a convincing manner that a reasonable
person would not hesitate to rely and act upon them. A reasonable doubt is
different from possible doubt because everything thing relating to human
affairs is open to some possible or imaginary doubt. Reasonable doubt is a kind
of doubt that is founded upon a real, tangible, substantial basis, and not upon
mere caprice or conjectures.
ATTEMPT A CRITICAL
ANALYSIS OF “KNOWLEDGE “, WITH EMPHASIS ON PLATO’S THEATETUS (201d), AND MENO
(98), AS FOUNDATIONAL LITERARY SOURCES .
In
the Theatetus, 201d, we are presented
with a sustainable inquiry into the subject matter of knowledge, in a bid to
answer the important question of what knowledge is especially as regards the
individually necessary and jointly sufficient conditions for knowledge.
In
this dialogue, Theatetus told Socrates that a man once told him that True
judgment with an account is knowledge, and True Judgment without an account
falls outside of knowledge. And things of which there is no account are not
knowable, while those which have account are knowable. This reveals that an
account of a true belief which is to account as knowledge must consist in
evidentially compelling and sufficiently grounded reasons in favour of such a
true belief.
In
the Meno, 98, we can trace some
textual evidence of the traditional notion of knowledge (JTB), wherein Socrates
asserts that “for true opinions, as long as they remain, are fine thing and all
they do is good. But they are not willing to remain, and they escape from man’s
mind, so that they are not worth much until one tie them down by giving an
account of the reason why. And that knowledge is recollection. After they are
tied down, they become knowledge, and then they remain in a place. That is why
knowledge is prized higher than correct opinion, and knowledge differs from
correct opinion in being tied down”. Knowledge as Justified True Belief (JTB)
thus emerges, and can be represented in a logical form as:
S
knows that P if,
I.
P
is true
II.
S
beliefs that P
III.
S
is justified in believing P
Belief
as one of the conditions for knowledge simply means, as used here, an
unsubstantial claim that a certain state of affairs obtains. The traditional
conception of knowledge sees belief as something inferior to knowledge, since
knowledge involves a justification of what is held to be the state of affairs,
but belief does not.
In
epistemology, the belief condition consists in holding a certain cognitive
content as true. Thus knowledge basically implies belief as one of its
important conditions, but a belief still needs truth and justification as
adjectival properties to qualify the belief.
Comments
Post a Comment