summary of Robert G. Hudson’s article ‘The Empirical Basis to Skepticism’ in the Minerva internet Journal of Philosophy Volume 11 (2007)
summary of Robert G. Hudson’s
article ‘The Empirical Basis to Skepticism’ in the Minerva internet Journal of
Philosophy Volume 11 (2007)
Lecturer: Rev. Fr. Joseph Ekong, O.P., Phd
Thesis statement:
Skepticism can be defended through an a
priori or an empirical way. But
empirical justification of skepticism is preferable.
Thesis Development
Non-empirical
approaches to skepticism usually take what Robert G. Hudson call the ‘consistency
approach’. This approach sees skepticism as justified because its assertion,
one might argue is consistent. The skeptical argument is this: we could be
wildly hallucinating right now, there could be a malicious evil demon with
god-like powers intent on deceiving us every step of the way, we could be wrong
in all ways imaginable, therefore, we lack knowledge of the world. This
argument is not very effective because the base logical possibility of such a
scenario is not a very enticing philosophy. Lots of circumstances are logically
possible – that I will live forever, that elephants will start growing wings,
and so on, hence the consistency approach does not take us too far. Because of
the apparent paucity of purely a priori,
logical defenses of skepticism, Hudson plans here to defend the view that to
support skepticism, the empirical approach needs to be considered.
The
main Cartesian support for skepticism for instance, the dream argument is an
empirical argument. It says that, since they are no (empirical) markers by
which we can distinguish dreams from reality, it follows that we do not know we
are experiencing reality. Similarly, David Hume’s argument for skepticism about
the existence of objective causation is an empirical argument. It says that, in
determining whether event A causes event B, we need to be able to determine
whether every instance of A is followed by an instance of B; but, since in the
usual case we lack access to such an enormous resource of data, we should be
skeptical about the existence of causal link between A and B. Another approach
to recognizing the empirical basis to skepticism is suggested by W.V.O Quine
who noted that empirical science renders skeptical hypotheses (the belief in
the existence of an evil genius bent on deceiving us) reasonable, given that
the scientific image of the world is markedly different from the intuitively
trustworthy, manifest image of the world. Tables appear solid but they are
actually filled with space, objects looked coloured but colour is only a
product of our minds. In other words, we learn through empirical inquiry.
If we
suppose for instance that there were certain distinguishing sights or sounds
exhibited only by dream experiences. The dream argument, by this very empirical
fact, would lack support. The crux of the dream argument as well as the Humean
argument is that we learn through experience that dreams are fundamentally
indistinguishable from reality and that we can never know if all event B follow
event A, respectively. Consider also a case where an empirically-grounded
scientific advance leads scientists to re-affirm the common sense view of the
world – scientists, let’s say, conclude that apparently solid objects are
solid, coloured objects are coloured, and so on. In such a situation, Quine’s
argument that scientific advance leads to a skeptical view would be turned
back.
Since
Hudson’s aim in this paper is to affirm the legitimacy of such an empirical
approach to adjudicating skeptical hypotheses, he addresses various objections
that might be advanced against such a strategy. The first objection concerns
the problem of vicious circularity. In particular, if empirical data succeed at
justifying the skeptical hypothesis, then how can such data be said to be
adequately justified, given that the skeptical hypothesis is affirmed? For if
skepticism is true, the empirical data supporting the skeptical hypothesis are
undermined, which in turn undermines the support provided for the skeptical
hypothesis. And from here we move in a circle because, if skepticism lacks
support, we restore the justifiedness of its empirical support and so again
justify skepticism. So, is such vicious circularity a serious problem for
empirical justification of skepticism?
The
first point to make here is that such a problem arises even If we provide an a priori justification for skepticism.
For instance, if one argues that skepticism is justified because it is a
consistent position, then of course the question arises whether we are
justified in believing that skepticism is a consistent position to begin with.
And again, if skepticism is true, we lose our justification for the claim that
it is consistent, and so thereby lose our justification for skepticism. Once
again, we move in a vicious circle.
Question
Can we now have any form of justification
for skepticism, if skepticism has the effect of denuding its own justificatory
support?
Robert
Hudson addressed this question when he says that empirical proof involves the
invocation of empirical claims in support of a hypothesis, where empirical
claims are defined as claims prompted by and describing observational
circumstances. This definition of an empirical claim, though accurate, is loose
and only suggestive. Nonetheless, it contains a core truth, which is that an
empirical claim need not be true in order for it to play a role in
justification. To make the truth of observational claims a requirement of
empirical justifiedness, would make empirical justifiedness a near
impossibility, and would obstruct the part of science. This is because as we
saw in Quine, the scientific image of the world differs markedly from the
manifest image.
Concerning
those who claim that the Cartesian dream argument is itself doubtful from a
skeptical perspective, Hudson replied that even if there are markers
distinguishing dreams from reality, we are unaware of them, and so we are no
further along in establishing our claim to knowledge. The skeptic’s reply is an
empirical argument – it rests in our lack of awareness of empirical markers
distinguishing dreams from reality, leaving aside their existence.
Furthermore,
one might argue that in the absence of relevant evidence, such as dreams,
hallucinations, and the like, skeptical hypotheses are worse than weakened but
plainly false. For, one might argue, the skeptical hypothesis essentially is
the hypothesis that what we take for perception is hallucinatory (or is
illusory, or is a dream, and so on), and so in a situation where there is a
complete absence of hallucinations, any skeptical hypothesis that trades in
hallucinatory episodes is not even possible. Here Hudson distinguished between
metaphysical hallucination where all our sensory experiences are illusory in
fundamental and striking ways, a state in which we are completely mistaken
about the nature of the world displayed by ordinary experiences, a state
deceptively generated by evil demons, vat scientists and the like. And by
contrast, ordinary hallucination, which is induced as we know by the ingestion
of various frungs, by excessive thirst and hunger, and so on. Given this
distinction, where we are considering a circumstances where we never endured
ordinary hallucinations, drawing the inference that skeptical hypotheses are
false would be fallacious, for it is possible to be in a state of metaphysical
hallucination while enduring no ordinary hallucination. Nevertheless, if we
never suffered ordinary hallucination, it would not be a compelling thesis to
say that we are metaphysically hallucinating. On the other hand however, it is
not inconsistent to state that we are metaphysically hallucinating where we
lack an empirical evidential basis.
Comments
Post a Comment