the arguments of Wasserstrom on legal ethics.


INTRODUCTION
According to Richard Wasserstrom, when a lawyer represents a client, he is obliged to defend the cause of the client. He is obliged to show indifference to the ends and the moral consequences of the ends sought by his clients.
The focus of this paper is on the arguments of Wasserstrom on legal ethics. For a better discussion of the subject matter, we shall begin with conceptual clarifications of legal ethics, morality in ethics using the idea of some philosophers, their argument towards morality. Next, we shall present Wasserstrom’s argument on legal ethics. We shall further highlight the arguments for and against his view on legal ethics.
LEGAL ETHICS
According to Stephen Pepper, when practising lawyers, law professors and scholars in the field of law speak of ‘legal ethics’, “they almost always are thinking about the ethics of the practice of law, the ethics involved in accomplishing legal work for clients.”[1]Alice Woolley states that the concern of legal ethics is not on the morality of lawyers, the morality of clients, or the morality of laws. Its concern “must be with what lawyers and clients do, not with who they are.”[2]Issues discussed in legal ethics focus on how lawyers should behave. Scholars of legal ethics grapple with the issues that buttress on the relationship between a lawyer and his client, and the relationship between a lawyer and the rest of mankind.
In legal ethics, there is a debate among legal ethicists whether a good lawyer can be a good person. Some scholars argue that ‘good lawyers’ by the virtue of their profession are obligated to seek the interests of their clients even when doing so would make them use the law to the prejudice of the weak or the innocent and detract from the common good. Others argue that the idea of legal boundaries does not provide an adequate protection against the harm lawyers cause others in the pursuit of the interests of their clients.[3] Richard Wasserstrom together with Charles Fried is among the scholars that argue that a good lawyer is under obligation to pursue the interest of his client. We shall focus on his arguments on legal ethics, with particular emphasis on lawyer-client relationship.
RICHARD WASSERSTROM’S ARGUMENTS ON LEGAL ETHICS
Richard Wasserstrom is an American Professor of Law and Professor of Philosophy from the University of California School Of Law, Los Angeles. In 1974, he delivered a lecture at “Amherst Collegeas a part of the Copeland Colloquium series on morality and the professions.”[4] This lecture was later revised and published as an article with the title, “Lawyers as Professionals: Some Moral Issues.”
In the above article, Wasserstrom examines the two moral criticisms levelled against lawyers. The first of these criticisms is based on lawyer’s relationship with the world at large. Some critics hold that the lawyer-client relationship makes lawyers to be amoral and at worst occasionally immoral in their dealings with the rest of mankind.[5] The second criticism focuses on the relationship between the lawyer and the client. Here, it is argued that the lawyer-client relationship is morally objectionable. This is so, because in this relationship the lawyer dominates and treats his client in both an impersonal paternalistic fashion.[6]
            In examining these criticisms, Wasserstrom asserts that a layer is a professional. As aprofessional, he is more subjected to criticism more than any other professional. By professional, he meant one who practises the professions that require a substantial period of formal education such as medicine or law.[7]Commenting on the first criticism on lawyers, Wasserstrom highlights that the major feature of every profession is the relationship between the professional and the client or patient. He calls the behaviour exhibited by each party in this relationship a “role-differentiated behaviour.”[8] For him, the nature of this role-differentiated behaviour makes a person in a particular role to put off one aspect of considerations, more especially moral considerations which otherwise would be relevant. Wasserstrom illustrates this point using the example of parent-child relationship. He argues that in every human culture, parents prefer the interests of their own children over the children of others. Thus, it is considered appropriate for a “parent to allocate excessive goods to his or her own children, even though the children of others may have substantially more pressing and genuine needs for these same items.”[9] He further asserts:
 If one were trying to decide what the right way was to distribute assets among a group of children all of whom were strangers to oneself, the relevant moral considerations would be very different from those that would be thought to obtain once one's own children were in the picture. In the role of a parent, the claims of other children vis-a-vis one’s own are, if not rendered morally irrelevant, certainly rendered less morally significant. In short, the role-differentiated character of the situation alters the relevant moral point of view enormously.[10]

According to Wasserstrom, a professional has to represent the interests of his client. The client has to be attended to, or looked after by the professional. This implies that the professional, like the parent is to prefer in various ways the interests of his or her client or patient over those of individuals generally.

WASSERSTROM ON THE LAWYER-CLIENT RELATIONSHIP
In the lawyer-client relationship, the lawyer is obliged to show indifference to the ends and the moral consequences of the ends sought by his client which the lawyer in ordinary situations would oppose. Wasserstrom opines that when a lawyer represents a client, the lawyer is obliged to make use of his expertise to achieve the end sought by his client. He is to do this “irrespective of the moral worth to which the end will be put or the character of the client who seeks to utilize it.”[11] In as much as the end sought by the client is not illegal, the lawyer is primarily amoral. It is his function as a legal professional to make his peculiar skills and knowledge available in accordance to the law to those with whom the relationship of client is established. [12] By way of comment, Wasserstrom is of the view that when a lawyer represents his client, he should not be concerned with the moral status of his client or the moral implication of the end which his client seeks. Even though in ordinary situation, the lawyer may strongly disapprove the ends sought by his client; but for the sake of his profession, he has the duty to defend the client. In this situation, the lawyer is an amoral technician. He is not interested about right or wrong.
Furthermore, Wasserstrom posits that when a lawyer agrees to represent a client, the lawyer is under an obligation to do everything he can to defend the client in trial irrespective of the lawyer’s belief in the client’s innocence. He further argues:
There are limits, of course, to what constitutes a defense: a lawyer cannot bribe or intimidate witnesses to increase the likelihood of securing an acquittal. And there are legitimate questions, in close cases, about how those limits are to be delineated. But, however these matters get resolved, it is at least clear that it is thought both appropriate and obligatory for the attorney to put on as vigorous and persuasive a defense of a client believed to be guilty as would have been mounted by the lawyer thoroughly convinced of the client's innocence.[13]

More so, Wasserstrom underscores that it is appropriate and obligatory for the attorney to employ a vigorous and persuasive argument in the defence of a client believed to be guilty. He should do this as though he is convinced of the client's innocence. Wasserstrom further highlights that in the course of defending his or her client, an attorney is permitted, as a part of his or her duty of representation, to make use of procedures and practices which are morally objectionable in themselves and which the lawyer in other situation will disapprove. For instance, in defending a client accused of rape, the attorney may insist that the accuser should undergo a psychiatric examination before trial. The results of the examination may help the lawyer prove that the offense never occurred. It is important to note that this is no longer permitted by law, but it was at the time Wasserstrom discussed this issue.[14]
For Wasserstrom, there is nothing wrong for a lawyer to represent a client whose aims and purposes are immoral. If the lawyer agreed to represent such a client, he is obliged to provide the best possible assistance, irrespective of his or her disapproval of the objective that is sought.[15] According to Wasserstrom, the job of the lawyer is “not to approve or disapprove of the character of his or her client, the cause for which the client seeks the lawyer’s assistance, or the avenues provided by the law to achieve that which the client wants to accomplish.”[16]The lawyer’s task however is to provide that competence which the client lacks and which the lawyer, as professional, possesses.[17]




WASSERSTROM ON THE MORAL PROBLEMS IN THE LAWYER-CLIENT RELATIONSHIP

Wasserstrom argues that the relationship between a lawyer and his client is a relationship of inequality. He is of the view that the role of lawyers often makes them form a paternalistic relation with their clients. They see themselves as people with special competencies and conceive their clients as objects – “as a thing to be altered, corrected, or otherwise assisted by the professional rather than as a person.”[18]The client’s inability to communicate in the language of the profession makes the client to be viewed less than a person in the lawyer’s eyes. Wasserstrom also notes that the lawyer relates with the client as though “the client were an individual who needed to be looked after and controlled, and to have decisions made for him or her by the lawyer, with as little interference from the client as possible.”[19]
            Regarding these paternalistic and impersonal attitudes of lawyers, Wasserstrom posits that they are the aberrant and not the usual characteristics of the lawyer-client relationship. He suggests that for there to be a desirable change, the legal language should be simplified. He also recommends that the legal processes should be made easier and more accessible to lay persons.[20]
            Many legal ethicists have reacted to Wasserstrom’s arguments. Some scholars accepted his view while some rejected it.
ARGUMENTS IN SUPPORT OF WASSERSTROM’S VIEW ON LEGAL ETHICS
Roy Cohn agrees with Wasserstrom that when a lawyer represents his client, he is obliged to protect the interest of his client. He opines that “it is not the lawyer’s responsibility to believe or not to believe - the lawyer is a technician . . . Law is an adversarial profession. The other side is out to get your client. Your job is to protect your client…”[21] Furthermore, George Sharswood supports Wasserstrom that the attorney should pursue the interest of his client irrespective of the moral status of the client or the moral worth of the objective which the client seeks. He argues: “the lawyer, who refuses his professional assistance because in his judgment the case is unjust and indefensible, usurps the functions of both judge and jury.”[22]Still on this, David Luban adds that it is not the duty of a lawyer to judge the morality of the client’s cause; for this is irrelevant to the morality of the representation. He notes that the official view of most lawyers is that the “lawyer’s morality is distinct from, and not implicated in, the client’s.”[23] He also argues that the client’s interest is more important than that of the rest of the world put together.[24]
            Furthermore, in support of the above arguments, Lord Henry Brougham in the speech made in his 1820 defence of Queen Caroline, has this to say:
An advocate, in the discharge of his duty, knows but one person in the world, and that person is his client. To save that client by all means and expedients, and at all hazards and costs to other persons, and, amongst them, to himself, is his first and only duty; and in performing this duty he must not regard the alarm, the torments, the destruction which he may bring upon others. Separating the duty of a patriot from that of an advocate, he must go on reckless of consequences, though it should be his unhappy fate to involve his country in confusion.[25]

Daniel Markovits also agrees with Wasserstrom that the job of a lawyer is to protect the interest of his client. He asserts: “Lawyers - at least when they function as adversary advocates - do not pursue justice itself, directly and impartially. Instead, they are charged loyally to represent particular clients, whose interests and aims may diverge from what justice requires.”[26]
ARGUMENTS AGAINST WASSERSTROM VIEW ON LEGAL ETHICS
            Notably, some legal ethicists do not totally agree with wasserstrom’s position on lawyer-client relationship. Stephen Pepper disagrees with Wasserstrom’s view that when a lawyer represents his client, he should not be concerned with the moral status of his client or the moral implication of the objective which his client seeks. Pepper argues that when the client has an end that is morally objectionable, the lawyer should initiate moral deliberation with the client. Similarly, he opines that when the client’s use of the law is morally wrongful, the lawyer ought to make it clear to him.[27]He further argues that in the just debt/technical defence situation, for instance, the lawyer might ask the client why he is considering resisting paying an admitted debtor is seeking advice about that possibility. He should find a “respectful way to initiate moral deliberation with the client regarding the debt and its repayment. The lawyer would explore with the client the fairness, justice, and morality aspects of the situation and options.”[28]
            Furthermore, Daniel Markovits does not support wasserstrom’s arguments that a lawyer should not be concerned with the moral worth of the end sought by his client even though they go against the moral beliefs of the lawyer. Markovits argues that the “Model Rules probably allow lawyers to refuse to argue against their most fundamental legal and moral beliefs, in particular by withdrawing from representations, or declining court appointments, that would require them to do so.”[29] For him, lawyers should be concerned with the objectives of their clients in order to ensure that their clients are not committing fraud. He affirms: “it is sometimes suggested that lawyers should be further required to make reasonable investigative efforts to ensure that their clients are not committing fraud.”[30]
MORALITY IN HOBBES
Hobbes holds that there is not anything that is absolutely good or evil, which means that there is nothing that is objectively good or objectively evil. What he believed was that what is good and what is bad is based on our appetite or desire which is as a result of the state of nature in man. Hobbes wrote:
“……..whatsoever is the object of any man’s appetite or desire; that is it which he for his part calleth good; and the object of his hate, and aversion, evil; and of his contempt, vile and inconsiderable. For these words of good, evil, and contemptible, are ever used with relation to the person that useth them: there being nothing simply and absolutely so; nor any common rule of good and evil, to be taken from the nature of the objects themselves; but from the person of the man (where there is no commonwealth;) or, (in a commonwealth,) from the person that representeth it; or from an arbitrator or judge, whom men disagreeing shall by consent set up, and make his sentence the rule thereof……”[31]
Good and evil are therefore relative notions for Hobbes. There is no absolute good and absolute evil and there is no common objective norm taken from the subjects themselves, to distinguish between good and evil. The rule for distinguishing good and evil depends on the individual; that is, on his voluntary motions if we consider man as he is part of the commonwealth or state. In the commonwealth, it is man who represents it, that is to say, the sovereign who determines what is good or what is evil. From the foregoing, it is clear that Hobbes’ notion of morality is “self-preservative”. Nature seeks a peaceful co-existence. Peace is achieved when we transfer our collective strength to a sovereign authority which is the Leviathan and then the social contract. For him, the purpose of morality is to ensure peace because peace is necessary condition for obtaining the satisfaction of one’s desires.[32] What move us according Hobbes are desires and aversions and the force behind these is self-preservation.[33] Self-interest prescribes that we avoid for example the beastly, brutal, and short state of Leviathan forms the source of right and wrong through the will of the Leviathan.[34]
MORALITY IN JEAN-JACQUES ROUSSEAU
Rousseau repeatedly claims that a single idea is at the center of his world view, namely, that human beings are good by nature but is rendered corrupt by society.[35] He criticizes Hobbes for assuming that the human in the “state of nature has no idea of goodness; he must be naturally wicked; that he is vicious because he does not know virtue.”[36] Rousseau assumes the opposite: in the natural state, humans have “uncorrupted morals“; not in the sense of a developed morality, but in the negative sense of a primitive morality that is not yet corrupted by society.[37] It is a state prior to any socialization. In this state, human beings are free, self-sufficient, and because of this they are still peaceful; they are capable of experiencing compassion, and they live in small biologically determined groups. Unfortunately, despite the alleged centrality of this claim, it is difficult to give it a clear and plausible interpretation. One obvious problem which is present from the beginning is that since society, the alleged agent of corruption, is composed entirely of naturally good human beings, how can evil ever get a foothold? It is also difficult to see what “natural goodness” might be. In various places Rousseau clearly states that morality is not a natural feature of human life, so in whatever sense it is that human beings are good by nature, it is not the moral sense that the casual reader of his writings would ordinarily assume.
HOBBES VERSUS ROUSSEAU
          Hobbes and Rousseau both make contrasting claims regarding the basic nature of humans in the absence of any social order. Hobbes argues that humans are born solitary and self-interested, void of any moral inclinations. By establishing that humans are all more or less equal in terms of skills and abilities, Hobbes derives the basic source of human conflict.[38] Rousseau also offers his views on the behavior of humans in their natural state, which are notably different from Hobbes’. While Rousseau may accept that Hobbes’ ideas may represent a modern human, he believes this is humans in an “artificial” state created by the society, and that the natural state is much different.[39] He claims that man in his natural state only strives for basic needs and will be content once those needs are met. Rousseau asserts that humans are naturally sympathetic to the suffering of other living beings and have moral issues with the suffering of others. This is sharply different from Hobbes’ views that humans are solely self interested.
Natural state is much different. He claims that man in his natural state only strive for basic needs and will be content once those needs are met. Additionally, Rousseau asserts that humans are naturally sympathetic to the suffering of other living beings and have moral issues with the suffering of others. This is sharply different from Hobbes’ views that humans are solely self-interested.
In summary, for Hobbes civilization saves us from ourselves. Without it we would regress to a beast-like state. For Rousseau, civilization is killing us. Thus, for Rousseau, the goal is to reclaim a more natural existence. While Thomas Hobbes emphasized man as self-interested, Rousseau insisted on the general will. 
Thomas Hobbes and J. J Rousseau developed theories on human nature and how men govern themselves. By way of the differing versions of social contract Hobbes and Rousseau agreed that certain freedoms had been surrendered for a society’s protection and emphasizing the government’s definite responsibilities to its citizens. Both philosophers created a revolutionary idea of the state of nature.
CONCLUSION
           
From the foregoing, we have seen the major arguments of Wasserstrom on legal ethics. He argues that in a lawyer-client relationship, lawyers are obliged to show indifference to the ends and the moral consequences of the ends which their clients seek. For him, when lawyers represent their clients, they are under obligation to pursue their clients’ interest.
We began this paper with a description of legal ethics. We noted in this paper that legal ethics concerned with the ethics involved in carrying out legal work for clients. It focuses on what lawyers and clients do and not on who they are. Furthermore, this paper discusses Wasserstrom’s view on legal ethics. According to Wasserstrom, the job of the lawyer is not to approve or disapprove of the character of his client, but his task is to provide that competence which the client lacks and which the lawyer, as professional, possesses.
This paper further discussed the arguments for and against Wasserstrom’s view. Legal ethicists such as Roy Cohn and David Luban agree with Wasserstrom that it is the duty of a lawyer to protect the interest of his client and not to judge the morality of the client’s cause. However, Stephen Pepper and Daniel Markovits argue against Wasserstrom’s position. Pepper argues that the when a lawyer represents a client whose objective is morally objectionable, the lawyer should initiate moral deliberation with him. More so, Markovits is of the view that when lawyers represent their clients, they should make reasonable effort to ensure that their clients are not committing fraud.







[1]Cf. Stephen Pepper,Locating Morality in Legal Practice: Lawyer? Client? The Law?”,Legal Ethics, Vol. 13, no.2,p. 174.
[2]Alice Woolley, “The Legitimate Concerns of Legal Ethics”,Legal Ethics, Vol. 13, no. 2,p. 168.
[3]Cf. Christine Parker, “Philosophical Legal Ethics: Ethics, Morals and Jurisprudence”, Legal Ethics, Vol. 13, no. 2,p. 165.
[4]Richard Wasserstrom, “Lawyers as Professionals: Some Moral Issues,” accessed on January 2, 2017, www. americanbar.org>administrative.
[5]Cf. Richard Wasserstrom, “Lawyers as Professionals: Some Moral Issues,” accessed on January 2, 2017, www. americanbar.org>administrative.
[6]Cf. Richard Wasserstrom, “Lawyers as Professionals: Some Moral Issues,” accessed on January 2, 2017, www. americanbar.org>administrative.
[7]Cf. Richard Wasserstrom, “Lawyers as Professionals: Some Moral Issues,” accessed on January 2, 2017, www. americanbar.org>administrative.
[8]Richard Wasserstrom, “Lawyers as Professionals: Some Moral Issues,” accessed on January 2, 2017, www. americanbar.org>administrative.
[9]Richard Wasserstrom, “Lawyers as Professionals: Some Moral Issues,” accessed on January 2, 2017, www. americanbar.org>administrative.
[10]Richard Wasserstrom, “Lawyers as Professionals: Some Moral Issues,” accessed on January 2, 2017, www. americanbar.org>administrative.
[11]Richard Wasserstrom, “Lawyers as Professionals: Some Moral Issues,” accessed on January 2, 2017, www. americanbar.org>administrative.
[12]Cf. Richard Wasserstrom, “Lawyers as Professionals: Some Moral Issues,” accessed on January 2, 2017, www. americanbar.org>administrative.
[13]Richard Wasserstrom, “Lawyers as Professionals: Some Moral Issues,” accessed on January 2, 2017, www. americanbar.org>administrative.
[14]Cf.Richard Wasserstrom, “Lawyers as Professionals: Some Moral Issues,” accessed on January 2, 2017, www. americanbar.org>administrative.
[15]Cf. Richard Wasserstrom, “Lawyers as Professionals: Some Moral Issues,” accessed on January 2, 2017, www. americanbar.org>administrative.
[16]Richard Wasserstrom, “Lawyers as Professionals: Some Moral Issues,” accessed on January 2, 2017, www. americanbar.org>administrative.
[17]Cf. Richard Wasserstrom, “Lawyers as Professionals: Some Moral Issues,” accessed on January 2, 2017, www. americanbar.org>administrative.
[18]Richard Wasserstrom, “Lawyers as Professionals: Some Moral Issues,” accessed on January 2, 2017, www. americanbar.org>administrative.
[19]Richard Wasserstrom, “Lawyers as Professionals: Some Moral Issues,” accessed on January 2, 2017, www. americanbar.org>administrative.
[20]Richard Wasserstrom, “Lawyers as Professionals: Some Moral Issues,” accessed on January 2, 2017, www. americanbar.org>administrative.
[21]David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 2007), p. 19.
[22]David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity.P. 20.
[23]David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity,p. 20.
[24]Cf.David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity, p. 23.
[25]David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity, p. 22.
[26]Daniel Markovits, A Modern Legal Ethics (New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 2008), p. 1.
[27]Stephen Pepper,Locating Morality in Legal Practice: Lawyer? Client? The Law?”,Legal Ethics, Vol. 13, no. 2, p. 174.
[28]Stephen Pepper,Locating Morality in Legal Practice: Lawyer? Client? The Law?”,Legal Ethics, Vol. 13, no. 2, p. 176.
[29]Daniel Markovits, A Modern Legal Ethics,p. 46.
[30]Daniel Markovits, A Modern Legal Ethics, p. 46.
[31] Thomas Hobbes, “Leviathan” ed. M. Oakeshott (Oxford: 1946)p. 4
[32] J.Omoregbe, “Ethics: A systematic and historical study” (Lagos:Jojaedu. Research and publishers 1993)p. 198
[33] Thomas Hobbes http://www.phil.cmu.edu/Cavalier/80130/part1/sect4/Hobbes.html1/04/2016
[34]Thomas Hobbes  http://www.phil.cmu.edu/Cavalier/80130/part1/sect4/Hobbes.html1/04/2016
[35] Jean-Jacques Rousseau http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rousseau/#ConHisMorPsy10/o4/2016
[36]JurgenBraungardt, “Jean-Jacques Rousseau and his philosophy”http://braungardt.trialectics.com/philosophy/political-theory/rousseau/08/04/2016
[37]J. J. Rousseau,The Social Contract, 1762, Book I Chapter 8
[38]David Mihal, “comparism of Hobbes’ and Rousseau’s views on social structure” http://dm-free-essays.blogspot.com.ng/2012/08/comparison-of-hobbes-and-rousseaus.html18/04/2016
[39]David Mihal, “comparism of Hobbes’ and Rousseau’s views on social structure” http://dm-free-essays.blogspot.com.ng/2012/08/comparison-of-hobbes-and-rousseaus.html18/04/2016



Comments

Popular posts from this blog

SUMMARY OF PROVIDENTISSIMUS DEUS, ENCYCLICAL LETTER OF POPE LEO XIII ON THE STUDY OF THE HOLY SCRIPTURE.

summary and appraisal of chapters one, two and three of the book The African Origin of Greek Philosophy: An Exercise in Afrocentrism, by Innocent C. Onyewuenyi.

THE LAST THREE WAYS TO PROVES GOD'S EXISTENCE BY THOMAS AQUINAS