WHY STUDY PHILOSOPHY OF LAW
Introduction
The
setting of Plato’s dialogue Crito is
the following: Socrates has been convicted of the crime of corrupting the youth
of Athens by teaching an impious about the gods. For this, he has been
sentenced to death by poison. He is now in prison waiting the time at which he
must drink the fatal cup. His friend and student Crito comes to visit him and explain that a “jailbreak” is all
arranged. Crito offers various
reasons as to why Socrates should escape. But is it right? Socrates asked. Is
it right for someone who has been convicted of a crime, even if he believes his
conviction was unjust to avoid punishment? More generally, is there an
obligation to obey the law, and what can be the basis for such an obligation?
The following questions are only answerable when one has understood what law is
in the light of philosophy. “Why study philosophy of law” is a question this paper
aims at answering. I begin with clarification of basic concept which leads us
to the scope of philosophy of law, followed by the relationship between law and
philosophy which provides us with the existential import as to why we ought to
study philosophy of law, and then conclusion.
Conceptual Clarifications
Philosophy:
Etymologically, philosophy is the combination of two Greek words, Philos (love) and Sofia (wisdom), which translates to mean lover of wisdom. It is
pertinent to note that there is no universal definition of philosophy and thus
relates to the fact that the more philosophers increase, the more such
definition is likely to increase. On the other hand, various definitions share
something in common with others. Philosophy can be said to be a rational,
critical and logical evaluation of a subject matter for the aim of acquiring
knowledge with leads to wisdom and happiness which is the goal of humans.
Law:
The question “what is law” has had long history and many answers has been given
to it. Many of these, however, are not alternative answers to the same
question, but answers to different questions about nature of law.[1]
Moreover, for Aquinas, law is a rule and measure of acts, whereby man is
induced to act or is restrained from acting: for lex (law) is derived from ligare
(to bind), because it binds to act.[2] In
order words, law is an ordinance of reason for the common good, promulgated by
him who has the care of the community.[3]
Philosophy
of Law: This is also known as legal philosophy
and is concerned with what the aim of law should be and also, of course, with
what the law can actually do. It also concerned with the permissible scope of
the law, with its limit.[4]
The Scope of Legal
Philosophy
Plato’s
dialogue Crito illustrates the fact
that the field of the philosophy of law overlaps with other branches of
philosophy. The Crito is not only one
of the classics of legal philosophy; it is also one of the classics of ethics
and political and social philosophy. The same holds for works by other writers,
for instance, Hobbes’s Leviathan.
There are no sharp lines of demarcation to the philosophy of law. Certain
problems are common to all these subjects, though they are often dealt with in
legal philosophy from a narrower perspective. This perspective also holds and
perhaps even more narrowly, for many works on “jurisprudence” which are devoted
to explaining the basic doctrines and principles of a given legal system.[5]
These works are nevertheless of philosophical interest. Still, because of the
ground they have in common, ethics and political and social philosophy has a
great deal to learn from philosophical inquiry into law. The study of moral
reasoning, for example, can be enriched by the study of legal reasoning.[6] The
philosophy of law also shares another features with the above mentioned
branches. It deals with two kinds of question:
normative (or justificatory) and analytic (or conceptual).[7]
Relationship
between Law and Philosophy
Philosophy
and law have a relationship shared among themselves as both are not devoid of
reason. Reason is the connecting factor for both philosophy and law. The
science of reason known as logic is a
tool employed in the domain of law for proper and critical evaluation of how
law ought to be. A just law is built on the foundation of good reason. Argument
for the justification of a particular law is brought to realization by logical
reason. Philosophy also obeys certain laws found in its domain in order to
provide a sound reason for propounding or choosing a particular theory.
Natural Moral Law
The term natural law refers to those moral insights
which man is able to know by means of his reason, independently of the verbal
revelation of God. It is of fundamental importance to know that the term
“natural” in this discuss has the meaning of (1) not supernatural, that is, not
communicated in a supernatural way; (2) not positive, that is, not result of
command of a legislative authority, as in positive human or divine law; (3)
found in and derived from the nature of man. These explanations show that the
doctrine of natural law deals with the question of natural ethics as a whole.
Natural law, the moral law of nature, natural ethics and natural morality are
synonyms.
Natural law doctrine is of
fundamental importance above all two on two accounts. First, it is the basis of
moral order of universal character and constitutes a source of ethical wisdom
which Christians share with all mankind, for its rest upon the reality which is
shared by all humans: their common humanity and existential conditions.
Secondly, natural law is the only adequate safeguard against arbitrary exercise
of political and legislative power. It is the final court of appeal against
unjust, prejudiced laws of human authorities. [8]
Why Study Philosophy
of Law?
Having
come this far in this paper, we are now faced with the epistemological question
as “why study philosophy of law? In answering the above question, I’ll begin by
stating that man in his nature is both a rational and social being. Man needs
the basic knowledge which makes him relate to issues in his/her social
consciousness. Again, since man is a political animal according to Aristotle,
he/she is fully involved with what goes on in his/her society. Perhaps, ignorance
is not an excuse for the law to take its due course. Philosophy of law as
earlier pointed out is concerned with what law ought to be and its application
to issues that arise in our society.
According
to Aquinas, lawmaking is a purposive activity. Its basis is the fact that
humans are goal-oriented. It is natural for creatures to seek ends that are
appropriate to its nature or essence. The fixing of the essences of things, and
of the inclinations of creatures toward end that complete their nature, is an
aspect of the divine governance of the universe, i.e., eternal law.[9] What gives content to the natural law is the
rational apprehension of the essence of man and the human good. Aquinas
developed this alongside Aristotelian lines that man is by nature a social
animal: he desires to live a life in common with other men, and he satisfies
his needs and wants only in co-operative enterprise with others.[10]
Augustine
in supporting Aquinas says:
“That
which is not just seems to be no law at all. Hence the force of a law depends
on the extent of its justice….Every human law has just so much of the nature of
law as it is derived from the law of nature. But if in any point it departs
from the law of nature, it is no longer a law but a perversion of law.” (Summa
Theologiae, I-II, q. 95)[11]
Hence,
studying philosophy of law is aimed at establishing justice through just laws
which is the end or goal of human beings. And so an unjust law will create
violence and make the goal of man unachievable.
Again,
the knowledge derived from philosophy of law will make man live a life of
virtue as Thomas Aquinas stated in his treatise on laws with particular
reference to the effect of law. He said:
“A
law is nothing else than a dictate of reason in the ruler by whom his subjects
are governed. Now the virtue of any subordinate things consists in its being
well subordinated to that by which it is regulated: thus we see that the virtue
of the irascible and concupiscible faculties consists in their being obedient
to reason; and accordingly the virtue of every subject consists in his
being well subjected to his ruler. So laws are meant to lead one to their
proper virtue”.[12]
Conclusion
From the forgoing, it has been evidently shown that
law cannot be removed from the existence of man. This is so given the fact that
man is a rational being and a political animal, for he/she is responsible for
what goes on his/her political environment. When made within the discourse of religion, ethics, political theory,
legal theory or philosophy of law, the claim that there is a natural law is an
offer to explain and defend certain claims often made, in different terms, in
the discourse of moral argument and choices, politics or law. In
pre-theoretical moral discourse, certain choices, actions or dispositions may
be asserted to be ‘inhuman’, ‘unnaturally cruel’, ‘perverse’ or ‘morally
unreasonable’. In pre-theoretical political discourse, certain proposals,
policies or conduct may be described as violations of ‘human rights’. In
international law and jurisprudence, certain actions may be described as
‘crimes against humanity’ and citizens may claim immunity from legal liability
or obligations by appealing to a ‘higher law’. The knowledge derived from law theory
offers to explain why claims of this sort can be rationally warranted and true.
It offers to do so by locating such claims in the context of a general theory
of good and evil in human life so far as human life is shaped by deliberation
and choice.
Bibliography
Aquinas, Thomas, Treatise
on Law (Summa Theological, Questions 90-97), U.S.A: Benziger Brothers,
Inc., 1965
Pagis, Anton G.
Basic Writings of St. Thomas Aquinas, ed. New York: Random House, 1954,
Vol. II, 784
Golding, Martin P., Philosophy of Law, U.S.A: Prentice-Hall, Inc., 1975
Wollheim, Richard,
“The Nature of Law,” Political
Studies, 2 (1954), 128-44.
[1] Richard Wollheim, “The Nature
of Law,” Political Studies, 2 (1954), 128-44.
[2] Thomas Aquinas, Treatise on
Law (Summa Theological, Questions 90-97), (U.S.A: Benziger Brothers, Inc.,
1965), P.3
[3] Cf. Martin P. Golding, Philosophy
of Law, (U.S.A: Prentice-Hall, Inc., 1975), P. 30.
[4]Cf. Ibid., p.3
[5] Ibid., p.2
[6] Martin P. Golding, Philosophy
of Law, (U.S.A: Prentice-Hall, Inc., 1975), Pg. 2.
[7] Ibid. pg. 2.
[8] Thomas Aquinas, Treatise on
Law (Summa Theological, Questions 90-97), (U.S.A: Benziger Brothers, Inc.,
1965),
[9]Cf. Martin P. Golding, Philosophy
of Law, (U.S.A: Prentice-Hall, Inc., 1975), P. 32.
[10]Cf. Ibid.
[11] Basic Writings of St. Thomas
Aquinas, Anton G. Pagis, ed. (New York: Random House, 1954), Vol. II, 784
[12] Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Treatise
on Law (Summa Theological, Questions 90-97), (U.S.A: Benziger Brothers,
Inc., 1965), P.31
Comments
Post a Comment